Science in Christian Perspective
Explanation, Testability, and the Theory of Evolution Part I
T. H.. LEITH
Department of Natural Science
Atkinson College, York University
Toronto, Ontario, Canada
From: JASA 32 (March1980): 13-17.
Introduction
Among scientists and analysts of science there is an
almost-universal acceptance
of the thesis that life has evolved over a lengthy span of
geological time and
that it continues to do so. A few heretics question this
interpretation, arguing
that the evidence supports at most intraspecies or intragenus
development with
the fossil record being best interpreted in non-evolutionary terms. Others,
though they operate within the usual consensus, differ on the
evolutionary sequences
suggested by paleontological and contemporary laboratory or field
information, This paper refers to each of these ideas only obliquely.
Our attention is turned instead toward a quite different sort of criticism,
the sort that takes exception to the way evolution has often been explained
and defended. Such censures exhibit considerable variety. Some question the
propriety of treating Darwin's own explanatory scheme as scientific
during the
half-century immediately following its appearance; others find
later, and even
current, theory equally unscientific by various standards. Some believe that
understanding in biology, and particu
larly in the interpretation of its historical data, is different
from the ways by which we comprehend the physical
world and that it is wrong-headed to attempt to fit evolutionary explanations
to forms appropriate only in the physical sciences. Others accept
current theory
as at least a fair sketch for explaining the factual material but deny that
the theory' provides, or at least intends to provide predictions by which it
can he tested.
This paper serves primarily as an examination of the explanatory structures
employed by evolutionary theorists and as a general evaluation of
the testability
of their schemes. The limits of space place constraints on the
breadth and depth
of toy inquiry, but sufficient analysis should be provided to give reasonable
warrant for my general conclusions. If they clarify the
similarities and contrasts
of theorizing in evolutionary work and in the physical sciences, and of the
kinds of things which count as their evidential support, I will he satisfied.
After all, must readers are not specialists when it comes to evolu
tionary technicalities and non-specialists commonly have qualms
about evolution,
if they have qualms at all, not because they can question
descriptions of (say)
evolutionary sequences with any competence, hot because they find
inadequacies
in the evolutionary explanations and in the standards of evidence employed by
advocates of the theory. Let me begin then by looking at
explanation as understood
among physical scientists both because it is widely considered the ideal and
because it will provide a context for my later comparisons with biology' and
evolution.
Explanation in Physical Science
In the physical sciences we explain experience when whatever we
wish to understand
is derived from laws and theories. These are themselves testable
within experience.
It is this testability throughout which separates physical science,
and anything
emulating it, from other attempts at explanation.
In one form, scientific explanation in physical science uses
statements described
as universal because they are corroborated by experiences which
appear to indicate
that conditions of a certain sort, whenever they occur, are
invariably accompanied
by conditions of another sort. One or more of such laws, together with a set
of circumstances found to be present, are used in practice to
deduce the presence
of conditions which we wish to explain. Thus, from the gas law for example,
together with a particular pressure which we know obtains, we may explain an
observed volume. Similarly, from the laws of gravity and motion as
well as from
information about the planets we may deduce the law of planetary motion; here
a more general law is used to explain one of more restricted application.
Sometimes, however, the covering laws or law won't
be universal in form but instead express probabilities
found by experience as when we state that p/q cases of A are cases of B. If
we know that something y is a case of A we may then conclude that,
with a probability
p/q, y is a case of B.
Physical science employs, as well, what we may call theoretical explanations.
Here a theory is proposed as an aid in understanding a set of laws found by
careful observation or experiment. The theory explains the
phenomena which exhibit
these regularities in terms of assumed laws governing the behavior
of imagined
entities and their activity and, by the use of interpretations of
these, indicates
how they are to be related to the phenomena. The theory is therefore used to
give a coherent and systematic account of a variety of different phenomena or
empirical laws while explaining why these apply only within certain
limits.
Sometimes this may be done by treating the theory as a set of
axioms, arid theorems
derived from these, together with interpretive rules by which the
theorems are
identified with empirical data. However, this technique often
proves to be exceedingly
difficult so that some model is employed to give an intelligible
interpretation
of the theory. For example a familiar physical system, having elements with
familiar properties which in turn exhibit relationships expressed in familiar
empiri
cal laws, may be used to give a suggested meaning to the entities
of the theory
and their activity. We must, of course, always be aware that these
theoretical
entities and processes actually involve ideas lying beyond the
familiar, ideas
often quite strange to the earlier modes of thought found in the model, but
which gain credibility by their employment in predicting empirical
laws previously
undiscovered.
The essence of all this is that, though laws perform a sort of
explanatory function
of their own, so that they are useful standing alone, scientists seek greater
understanding through explaining the laws in terms of more general
laws or theories.
Here there is a binding requirement. As the strength of our
purported explanation
depends upon the confidence which we can place in the covering laws
or theory,
and as that is a function of the degree of corroboration which they
have achieved
in the face of severe testing, we must take pains to keep our covering laws
or theory both testable and tested.
It is here that many explanations which are unlike those of physical science
fail grandly, for, when we turn from explanation to prediction, the laws or
theories which they employ, not being falsifiable by experiment or
observation,
predict everything and nothing. This is because they cannot indicate what it
is in experience that would be different were they untrue. Thus, for example,
an explanation of the events of the world as due to the will of God
will ordinarily
have no prognostic utility; as a consequence the explanation is
untestable and
on that account would appear to many to be unworthy of rational belief. This
result may be avoided if we somehow had a prior knowledge of God's will or if
we believe the explanation because it follows from a broader set of beliefs
which have their own justification. In the former case fulfilled prediction
would provide the vehicle by which the explanation gains credibility while,
in the latter, the explanation gains support in spite of its
inability to anticipate
events.
Is Explanation in Evolution Different?
It has been argued that evolutionary explications are rather like this second
example; they are neither explanatory nor corroborahle in the style
of the physical
sciences, yet they are supported sufficiently well to command
widespread acceptance.
Later I examine the part of this thesis which claims that
evolutionary theorizing
lacks the ability to predict, but here it is the different
structure of explanation
and mode of evidential undergirding which are purportedly characteristic of
this theorizing which calls for comment.
(a) The Use of Narrative
Several decades ago Beckner1 described a characteristic of
evolutionary interpretations
of the history of life which, in his opinion, inevitably marked much of the
writing of paleontologists and historical geologists. It was a
description which
others have found to be fitting. For Beckner and his fellows the past is made
intelligible largely through the use of narrative passages,
together with loose
argument, connecting occasional and brief attempts at deductive argument in
the style of the physical scientist.2 This emphasis upon narrative explanation is apparently
made necessary
by the uniqueness of the events which comprise the evolutionary
history of living
things; because events differ from one another in significant ways
they cannot
be instances of laws and most then be explained by pointing out and
describing
the sequence of circumstances which seem to have preceded or
accompanied them.
It is worth noticing in passing, however, that narration might be
widely employed
in evolutionary interpretation for reasons other than the nature of
the events
being discussed. For one thing, the narrative may, on inspection, prove to he
more a description of the scheme which unraveled a puzzle than an
argument supporting
the interpretation. The process of decipherment, unfolding "the context
of discovery" as analysts of science would call it, may he mistaken for
the "context of justification." This is particularly
likely if one's
writings are intended to instruct and to convince the reader by leading bins
or her along the sort of path which the writer found useful in
arriving at some
particular insight. As another example, the complexity of the occasions being
dealt with and the lack of so much desirable information in the fossil record
might make the use of a highly-descriptive account convenient as an
explanation
sketch. It would appear then that the narrative form is sure to be a familiar
one in the literature of evolution, as Beckner and those like him
have claimed.
The question remains whether the form is unavoidable whenever an
understanding
of evolution is attempted.
Let us first look briefly at the idea that evolutionary events are unique for
this, we saw, was used as a constraint by some which they claimed prevented
the use of explanatory schemes used in physical science. The difficulty which
at once comes to mind is that "unique" must be defined by including
the specifications under which the terns is to apply. Buddy Rich,
for example,
is unique in drumming skills but not in being American, male, or
over 50 years
of age. Likewise, the disappearance of the last saber-toothed tiger is unique
in that it occurs only once but it is not unique if treated as an example of
the disappearance of a life form by the processes of natural
selection. An event's
character then depends upon the scheme under which it is described.
If this is so, it is far from obvious that evolutionary explanations cannot
be arrived at within which any historical event can be employed without the
question of the event's uniqueness ever arising. In a similar way, whether an
event is an instance of a law depends upon how specifically we describe it.
Any event may he specified in such a way as to be non-recurring and thus an
instance of none of the usual laws of science. Described, though, in suitable
ways any event may become an example of one or more of these laws. It would
seem, then, that description of evolutionary events might he developed which
would enable its to see them as examples of evolutionary laws of some kind.
If so, the thesis that evolutionary explanation does not employ
laws is either
true or false in fact but no principle seems to prevent the
possibility.3
If there might he evolutionary laws the case for the necessity of narrative
explanation, on the grounds that they can't exist, collapses. Those
who defend
this form
of explanation most then argue that such laws are so rare that they can play
little part in evolutionary understanding. We shall now see, however, that,
if evolutionary laws are so difficult to come by, evolution would be devoid
of explanation as much by narrative description as by covering
laws! The reason
is that narration seems to be impossible without at least a
disguised utilization
of law, a constraint which has been pointed out b various writers.4
Let us suppose that explanation in an historical area like paleontology means
the presentation of a sufficient number of relevant circumstances preceding
or accom
panying an event, that is "E because C1, C2, Q3 . The
measure of sufficiency is that the event could reasonably have been predicted
had we known C1, C2, C3 .... ; thus "If C1 , C2, C'. .. then
E." The
probability which we may claim for our prediction depends upon the number of
relevant circumstances which our narrative provides. Dray, who
argues for explanation
in this style, calls this ground for F an "inference rule."5
Compare this with the covering law model employed in physical science: one or
more laws L1 , L9, L3 ... together with a set of relevant circumstances C1,
C2, C3...
allows its to infer event E. (If the laws are statistical, we may
conclude that
there is a certain probability of F). Dray clearly wishes to remove laws from
the explanatory schema and to replace them by a role for moving
from the circumstances
to the event directly, However, as Hemspel6 has noted, not only is the
move often difficult or impossible, hot it seems apparent that we are merely
moving from one form of empirical generalization to another. The
inference role
is less like a role in chess than a role such as meteorologists might use in
discussing the weather; it is a sort of law experientially derived, subject
to change when new insights in science alter our view as to which conditions
are relevant to an event and modified each time the conditions
which are described
vary in number.
Looking at narrative accounts from a different perspective leads to similar
conclusions. Let us suppose that we are offered an explanation of the origin
of some property of a group of organisms such as Goudge's account
of the origin
among amphibians of limbs suited to locomotion on land. We are told a story
of drought and of the necessity to find water which resulted in an advantage
for these animals capable of moving from pool to pool, an advantage which by
accident permitted them to remain on land. Unfortunately, as Ruse7
has noticed,
the account provides no understanding of such things as how limbs might have
developed, nor of why amphibians needed to remain in water
initially yet could
eventually remain on land. The probable explanation of these calls
for the use
of laws such as those of natural selection and genetics and of
adaptive advantage.
As these are all arrived at by modern studies and carried hack into the past
they cannot be reduced to the language of historical narrative.
It appears that the case for narrative as the explanatory model for evolution
is not easily made. Explanation by the use of scientific laws appears to be
unavoidably present. Two further illustrations should re-enforce
this observation.
(i) Inherent in narrative attempts at describing events there is a tendency
toward classification in spite of frequent reference to the
uniqueness of historical
happenings. If this classification is to avoid arbitrariness and is
to he explanatory
it would seem that sonic general pattern of understanding must be employed;
and this pattern can hardly he anything more than a covering law,
(ii) Narrative explanation also carries with it the isnplication
that each step
in an account can be shown to lead to the next, at least with
reasonable likelihood.
Surely this calls for the use of some covering law which makes the appearance
of each stage predictable given what has preceded it.8
It is evident that whenever narration is employed in an explanatory role in
evolution it reduces to either a simplified account, called for by the need
for brevity or by a lack of information, or to a combined and
informal presentation
of the initial conditions arid lawful premises which appear to make
some event
which is of interest intelligible. All of these are necessary in telling the
story of the history of life; hence the wide use of the style.
(b) Non-Scientific Explanation
We have been looking at the thesis that evolutionary explanation of
the paleontologieal
record is different from that found in the physical sciences but is
nonetheless
scientific Now we must explore briefly the quite different argument, offered
by several writers, that evolutionary explanation of not only historical data
but also of contemporary living things is not scientific at all.9 In essence
this means that it is supposed that the theory contains no laws,
that it lacks
theoretical entities, and that the theory is not testable and consequently is
not revisable in the light of experience. In examining this view, I comment
only on Manser's version.
Manser begins by sharply distinguishing Darwin's
concept of evolution from what we may call Mendelian genetics,
later introduced
into Darwinism as a specific assertion about the sneehanism of
variation where
the original concept had needed to say nothing. Evolution is
explained in Darwinian
terms, as Manser summarizes it, by structural variations which are
inheritable
appearing randomly with respect to any benefits they confer, by
natural selection
where the environment (internal or external) as related to some variation is
more beneficial than to others, by selection conferring on those
with more beneficial
variation the capacity to survive and to reproduce themselves more
successfully
than others lacking these variations, by these benefits likely resulting in
more numerous progeny, and by inheritance distributing the
beneficial variation
throughout the population.
As with any explanation of evolution, evolution is of course
accepted as a fact
by Darwinism; it states the way that environmental selection and
variation are
related and shows how it leads to the evolution of organisms. It is
not, though,
in Manser's opinion, a set of premises from which predictions may
be made, with
the result that it isn't testable. In form, it is a scheme of
categories conceptually
related to one another into which we place
examples derived from a study of living and fossil forms so that we explain
them in evolutionary terms. It formulates no laws and its terms are defined
circularly. For example, we cannot predict the fitness of an
organism to survive,
as the theory offers no criteria, but we can assert instead that an organism
which has survived is fittest, and fittest because the organism had certain
characteristics which were suited to the environment in a special way so that
the organism gained an advantage over its competitors.
If Darwinian evolution is to show no more than how, after events
have been discovered
and described, they may be categorized so as to reveal their
evolutionary relationship
to one another, it is necessary that the scheme cannot be expressed
in the theory
form sketched in the first section of this paper. This is so because, should
Darwinian be expressible by a set of axioms, the theorems deduced
are predictions
and thus are potentially testable. In fact, Darwinism can he
expressed in just
this fashion: in an important paper almost 30 years ago (and 16 years before
Manser's papers), Mary Williams provided a short set of axioms which include,
or from which can he deduced, all the statements of Darwinian evolution.10 The
nonscientific appears to be scientific after all.
There is, though, a catch here because the theorems which Williams
derived were
so general as to he to all intents untestable. It would require a great deal
of work to state an improved set of axioms necessary for deriving much more
specific, and thus testable, consequences. The alternative is a
less-rigorous,
a rather intuitive, derivation of these predictions from the
original set.11
Surely that shouldn't bother us too greatly for much of even a
"hard science"
like physics is in the same position; for example, we explain empirical laws
within Newtonian mechanics, just as Newton did in the Principia, in a quite
intuitive and nonrigorous manner in our classes and textbooks.
Nonetheless it is a fact that many remain convinced, if I may judge
from numerous
letters and conversations, that evolution appears in too many ways
to be untestable.
Perhaps this is due to a lack of knowledge as to just what
testability accrues
to the intuitively-derived predictions of Darwinian theory, or of that theory
cum genetic principles, as well as to the application of laws
within evolution.
We shall look at these accruals in due course, but, whatever the
reason, a thesis
such as Manser's meets with considerable sympathy. Others equally
bothered have
turned to Sir Karl Popper, the leading modern advocate of testability as the
criterion demarcating scientific discourse, to determine whether evolutionary
theory might be otherwise understood. With Popper they conclude that it is a
metaphysical speculation.12
(e) Metaphysical Explanation
As is by now well-known, Popper opposes the view that science may
properly ever
claim to have grasped the essential character of nature's patterns
and regularities.
Likewise, he stands in opposition to the alternative instrumentalistic thesis
that science shouldn't attempt to explain nature save in the sense
of inventing
whatever useful fictions result in correct prediction. His own view is that
science properly makes tentative suggestions as to what
is going on in the world, suggestions which may be true but at best
can he shown
to he corroborated by severe testing. At worst they are falsified
by experience,
with the advantage however of teaching us ways by which nature does
not function.
The Popperian view may then be called Jallibilism.13
The line between science and other claims to understand our world
is now drawn
in these terms. Science stands as the composite of actual and
potential fallible
explanations which are open to severe testing, that is testing
which could well
show them to be false. All else is unfalsifiableincluding essentialistic and
instrumentalistic, as well as Popper's own, evaluations of how to do science.
However, Popper is scarcely likely to treat Zen Buddhism and the hundreds of
pages of defence of his fallibilistic model as on a par; we find that he does
not, for he takes one to be far more open to critical application
than the other.
For example, his view of science may be compared with its
competitors to determine
which best fosters open-minded research and which hinders most the retention
of error. Likewise, metaphysical speculations may he judged among
other things,
in terms of the degree to which they support science or suggest
scientific theories
and directions of scientific study.14
In this light we may understand Popper's comment that "Darwinism is not
a testable scientific theory but a metaphysical research programme-a possible
framework for testable scientific theories."15 We may also realize just
why Popper has invested considerable effort into developing his own
explanation
of the trends found in the fossil record: a suggested improvement
in presentday
evolutionary theory which, in his opinion, cannot make sense of
such directional
sequences.
But why does Popper consider contemporary theory on evolution
metaphysical rather
than merely scientifically insufficient? Presumably because the
theory is untestable
in areas even where it seems to make sense. Popper provides several examples,
each of which he feels exhibits a failure of the theory to predict and thus
to explain (he believes that if we cannot say "If such and such had been
the case then this would have been predicted," we cannot say "This
occurred because such and such is the case").16
One example is the evolution of variety (speciation) where he thinks we can
merely report that certain species were apparently adapted
sufficiently to survive
but we could not predict that these alone, or indeed that any,
would have survived.
Another is the idea which we mentioned earlier that fitness to
survive (adaptability)
is measured by actual survival but would not have been predicted. Lastly, he
argues that we cannot predict any specific evolutionary change so that when
we find sudden changes in fossil forms we can only claim that, in
light of current
doctrine, we should look for an explanation in terms of a missing record of
small and accumulating mutational events.
Each of these is discussed at length in a recent paper by Ruse.17 As he
properly points out, all that is necessary to refute Popper's
thesis is to report
actual predictions in each case which have been tested or which are open
to testing in some future research programs. This Rose does; consequently the
illustrations point up issues which lie within science so that
speciation, adaptability
and rates of evolutionary change are not merely metaphysical
concepts as Popper
claims.18 I might add that this does not prevent the concepts being given
additional metaphysical interpretations whose worth, or lack of it, must he
assessed on appropriate grounds but that is quite another matter.19
In suns, then, Popper has failed to show that evolutionary
explanation is either
non-scientific or metaphysical on his own criteria. With Ruse I would put the
failure down to Popper's being poorly informed about current work
in evolution
and not to his criteria. They remain invaluable tools for further
work in demarcating
science from other things.
(To be continued.)
REFERENCES
1M. Beckner, The Biological Way of Thought, Columbia Univ. Press, New York,
1959.
2Compare TA. Coudge, The Ascent of Life, Univ. of Toronto Press, Toronto,
1961 and "Causal Explanations in Natural History," Brit. Jour. for
the Phil. of Sci., Vol. 9, 1959-60, pp. 194-202: It. Burhenn, "Narrative
Explanation and Redescription," Can. Jour, of Philosophy, Vol. 3, 12/73,
pp. 419-425; DR. Kitts, The Structure of Geology, Southern
Methodist Univ. Press,
Dallas, 1977, pp. XV, 91-92; L. Goldstein, "A Note on
Historical Explanation,"
Philosophy of Science, Vol.42,9/75, pp. 312-319; and SW. II. Dray, Laws and
Explanations in History, Oxford Univ. Press, London, 1966. K.
Popper, The Poverty
of Historicism, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1963, p. 108 refers to
the uniqueness of evolutionary events but does not espouse
narrative explanation.
His position will he discussed later in this paper.
3D. Hall, Philosophy of Biological Science, Prentice-Hall Inc.,
Englewood Cliffs,
NJ., 1974 suggests some of these points also.
4D. Hull, op. cit.; C. C. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation, Free
Press, New York, 1965, pp. 44611 and his "Explanation and Prediction by
Covering Laws" in B. Banmrin (ed., Philosophy of Science, Vol.
1, Inteescience
Publishers, 1963, pp. 107-133; 11. Lehman, "On the Form of Explanation
in Evolutionary Theory," Theon'a, Vol. 32, 1966, pp. 14-24; M.. Ruse, "Narrative
Explanation Revisited," Can, Jour, of Philosophy, Vol. 4,
3/75, pp. 529-533
and his earlier "Narrative Explanation and the Theory of
Evolution,"
Can. Jour, of Philosophy, Vol. 1, 9/71, pp. 59-74, "Is the
Theory of Evolution
Different?" Scientia, Vol. 106, 1971, pp. 765-783, 1069-1093,
and The Philosophy
of Biology, Hutchinson, London, 1973.
5Dray, Laws. Compare M. Scriven, "Explanation & Prediction
in Evolutionary
Theory," Science, Vol. 130, 28/8/59, pt, 477-482 and "Explanations,
Predictions and Laws." In H. Feigl and C. Maxwell (eds.),
Minnesota Studies
in the Philosophy of Sciences, Vol.3, Univ. of Minn, Press,
Minneapolis, 1962.
6Hempel, Aspects, p. 357.
7Ruse, "Narrative Explanation and the Theory of
Evolution" and "Is
the Theory of Evolution Different?.," pp. 1084-1090.
8See Hempel, Aspects, p.446.
9A. B. Manser, "The Concept of Evolution," Philosophy,
Vol. 40, 1/65,
pp. 18-34; AD. Barker, "An Approach to the theory of Natural
Selection," Philosophy, Vol. 44, 10/69, pp. 271-290 (a sympathetic discourse (in Manser's
paper); and J.J.C. Smart, Philosophy and Scientific Realism, Routledge &
Kegan Paul, London, 1963. An attitude similar to Manser's is found
in PA. Hayek,
"Degrees of Explanation," Brit. Jour. for the Phil. of Sri., Vol.
6, 195,5-56, pp. 209227.
10M. Willianss, "Deducing the Consequences of Evolution: A Mathematical
Model," Jouru. of Theor. Biol. , Vol. 29, 1949, pp. 343-385.
11See M. Wilhams, "Palsifiahle Predictions of Evolutionary Theory,"
Philosophy of Science, Vol. 40, 1973, pp. 518-537.
12K. Popper, "Darwinism as a Metaphysical Research Programme"
in PA. Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Vol. 1, Open Court Pub.
Co., La Salle, Illinois, 1974, pp. 133-143 and his Objective
Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, Oxford Univ. Press, London, 1975, pp. 242 ff.
13See my "Notes on the Predispositions of Scientific Thought
and Practice,"
this journal, Vol. 24, 6/72, pp. 51-57 for an outline. Detail is provided in
Popper's The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson of London,
1959; in his Conjectures & Refutations, Routledge & Kegan Paul.
London, 1963, pp. 66-96, 164-200, 253-292; in the Schilpp volumes (see note
12); in B. Magee, Popper, Fontana Books, Clasgow, 1975; and in B. Ackermaon,
The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Univ. of Mass., Amherst, 1975.
14
Compare J . 0. Wisdom. ''Scientific theory: empirical Content,
Embedded Ontology,
and Weltsoischannrsg,'' Phil. Phenom. Research, Vol. 33, 1972, pp 62-77 and
"Metaphysics & Verification- in John Wisdom, Philosophy &
Psychoanalysis, Univ. of California, Berkeley 1969; P. Quay, "Progress
as a Demarcation Criterion for the Sciences," Philosophy of Science, Vol.
41, 1974, pp. 154-170; "Popper's Account of Acceptability," Anal.
Jour. Phil., 1971, pp. 167-176; C. Hartshorne "Present
Prospects for Metaphysics," Monist, Vol. 47, 1963, pp 155210; K. Nielsen, "Metaphysics and
Verification
Revisited," Southwestern Jour. Phil., Vol. 6, 1975, pp. 75-94;
II. Hochberg.
"Metaphysical Explanation," Meta philosophy, Vol. 1,
1970, pp. 139-165.
J. Walker "The Tolerability of Metaphysics," Internat.
Phil. Quart.,
Vol. 13, 1973, pp. 5-2,3; and J.W.N. Watkins, "Confirmable and
Influential
Metaphysics," Mind, Vol. 67, 1958, pp. 344-365.
15Popper, "Darwinism," p. 134.
16Ibid., pp. 136-138.
17M. Ruse, "Karl Popper's Philosophy of Biology,"
Philosophy of Science,
Vol. 44, 12/77, pp. 638-661.
18Compare M. Ruse, "Confirmation and Falsification of Theories of
Evolution," Scientia, Vol. 104, 1969, pp. 329-357 and Z.
Kochanski, "Con
ditions and limitations of Prediction-Making in Biology,''
Philosophy of Science,
Vol. 40, 1973, pp. 28-51.
19See M. Beckner, The Biological Way; Al. Crene & F.
Mendelsohn (eds.),
Topics in the Philosophy of Biology, Beidel, Dordrecht, 1976; 1).
Hull, Philosophy;
M. Ruse, Philosophy; J. Msusorl, Chance & Necessity, Collins,
London, 1972;
B. Bensch, Rio philosophy, Columbia Univ. Press, New York, 1971; W. Elsasser,
Chief Abstractions of Biology, N. Holland Pub, Co., Amsterdam,
1975; F .Ayala
and T. Dobzhansky, Studies in the Philosophy of Biology, Univ. of California
Press, Berkeley, 1974; S.F. Smith, Philosophy of Biology, St. Johns
Univ. Press,
New York, 1967 and his Philosophical Problems in Biology, same
publisher, 1966;
3,f. Crene, The Knower and the Known, Faber and Faber, London,
1976, her Understanding
of Nature which is Vol. 23 of Boston Studies in the Phil. of Sci.
and her Interpretations
of Life and Mind, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1971, which all contain
discussions of metaphysical questions. From the large journal literature the
following topics are illustrative: G. de Laguna, "The Role of Teleonomy
in Evolution," Philosophy of Science, Vol. 29, 4/62, pp.
117-131; L. Wright,
"Explanation & Teleology," Philosophy of Science,
Vol. 39, 1972,
pp. 2114-218 and Vol. 42, 1975, pp. 299-306; M Beckner, "Function and
Teleology," Jour. Hst. Biol., Vol. 2, 1969, pp. 151-164; 1'.
Scluevella,
"Emergent Evolution & Reductionism," Scientia, Vol. 67, 1973,
pp. 323-3,30; 54. Beckner "Metaphysical Presupposition ant]
the Description
of Biological Systems,'' Synthese, Vol. 15, 1963, pp. 260-274; A. Plamonstsin,
"The Contemporary Reconciliation of Mechanism and Organicism," Dialectics,
Vol. 29, 1975, pp. 213-221; H. Hein "The Endurance of the Mechanism-Vitalistic
Controversy," Jour. Hist. Biol., Vol. 5, 1972, pp. 159-185;
and F. Ayala,
"Biology as an Autonomous Science," Amer. Scientist, Vol. 56, 1968,
pp. 207-221.