Science in Christian Perspective
The Behaviorist Bandwagon and the Body of Christ
Ill. A Christian Examination of Applied Behaviorism
MARY STEWART VAN LEBUWEN
Department of Psychology
York University
From: JASA 31 (September 1979): 129-138.
In Part I of this paper, we attempted to explain the nature of the behaviorist
enterprise by distinguishing among (a) behaviorism as a total world
view ("ontological
behaviorism"), (b) behaviorism as a set of research principles for guiding
laboratory investigation of human and animal behavior
("methodological behaviorism"),
and (c) behaviorism as a marketable tool for changing behavior in the world at
large ("applied behaviorism"). In Part II, we were
particularly concerned
to examine the implications of ontological behaviorism for the
thoughtful Christian.
We attempted to show that the assumptions of determinism,
materialism, and "mental processlessness," to which the ontological behaviorist adheres,
are incompatible
with the biblical view of man: environmental determinism leaves no
room for moral
accountability; materialism leaves no room for spiritual realities over and above what is reducible to
the purely physical; "mental processlessness" leaves no
room for activities
such as reasoning, feeling, or creatively imagining - activities which we know
to be characteristic of God himself and therefore (however
imperfectly) of human
beings made in His image. Moreover, we pointed out that ontological
behaviorists
themselves, once they bump up against created reality, cannot
themselves consistently
live up to the assumptions of their position: in one way or another, autonomous
man, morally-accountable man, thinking man, spiritually oriented man returns to
the behaviorist system which claims to have dispensed with him. This
is a further
reason for questioning the validity of this "new gospel."
However, the serious flaws of ontological behaviorism do not alter the fact that the applied techniques of behaviorism are everywhere
around us, are much used, and in many ways apparently "work." Since,
as we have already pointed out, the applied behaviorist does not
necessarily adhere
to behaviorism as a total world view, perhaps we need to examine the
track-record
of applied behaviorism separately, trying to distinguish those components which
a Christian may feel at ease in using from those towards which he should turn
a skeptical eye. We will begin with some typical examples and standard working
principles of behavior modification techniques, then go on to suggest
what Christians
might accept and reject from the system, and why. The following
examples are based
on techniques of operant conditioning exclusively, since it is these techniques
that the lay reader is most apt to see being applied in schools,
clubs, and homes.
The application of respondent conditioning techniques, as described in Part I
of this essay, is still largely restricted to the professional
therapists' office
and to very selective institutional settings.1
Applied Behaviorism: Some Typical Examples
Let us return to Billy, the autistic child whose bizarre, unmanageable behavior
was described at the beginning of Part I of this paper. When I first met Billy,
although I had only a modicum of training in the techniques of
behavior modification
I spent some time showing Billy's parents how certain (essentially
simple) principles
of behavior modification could be used to "shape" socially desirable
actions in their son and at the same time "extinguish" his
bizarre habits:
since he was a good eater, I simply took charge of his food dish while he was
captive in his highchair and made each spoonful contingent on his emitting some
approximation to the word "food." To begin with, I promptly rewarded,
or "reinforced" any chance grunt with a mouthful of food, but as the
child began to make the association between vocalizing and getting
food, I could
begin to require progressively more of him: not just any grunt, but
only an "oo-o"
sound would then be rewarded, and a little later, only an "oo-d" and
finally, only the entire word "food." In less than 10 minutes, Billy
was saying a word, and (just as important) paying close attention to
another human
being. As an amateur behavior modifier, I had made use of essentially the same
principle as animal trainers use to teach circus animals complicated
tricks: one
begins by rewarding remote approximations to the final "trick" - bits
of behavior which the animal is likely to display anyway in the normal course
of its activities, and once these "simple" behaviors can be reliably
elicited by the food treats, the trainer can gradually require more
and more complicated
behavior for the same reward until the tiger is finally waltzing with the bear,
or (a much-quoted example from B.F. Skinner's Harvard laboratory) the pigeons
are playing ping-pong with each other by batting a celluloid ball
back and forth
across a table with their beaks. Of course, the pigeons don't "know"
that they're playing a game called ping-pong, nor did Billy
"know" that
the noises he was emitting constituted a real word in a real language
that could
be used to communicate - but in the case of autistic children like Billy, what
begins as a mere noise emitted to food which cannot be obtained any other way
can gradually be taught to be used as a label, then as part of a
request or question,
and eventually as part of a real (albeit still somewhat mechanistic)
conversation.
Another example: a severely regressed schizophrenic woman has been vegetating
on the back ward of a mental hospital for years, unreachable by more
traditional
forms of therapy, spending what time she is not eating or sleeping in
the endless
repetition of bizarre phrases and actions, apparently almost totally oblivious
to the real world around her. Then the hospital institutes a behavior
modification
program. The behavior modifiers point out that, far from helping the woman by
tolerating or even indulging her bizarre behavior, the hospital staff
are effectively
rewarding, or "reinforcing" it, in the first place by giving her food
and shelter while she persists in it, and secondly by paying attention to her
when she engages in it. Suddenly the entire working operation of the
ward changes.
The woman discovers, for instance, that she will not get a meal
until, for example,
she begins to use the toilet for defecation instead of soiling herself. To the
surprise of the skeptical ward attendants (who have been cleaning her
up for years),
she is toilet trained within days. A little later, she is made to
"earn"
yard privileges (or cigarettes, or candy, or whatever she finds
particularly rewarding)
by washing and dressing appropriately. Still later, she learns to
hold a coherent
conversation, or help with tasks around the ward, and
"earns" not direct
rewards, but plastic poker-chips, a sort of "local
currency," with which
she can "buy" a number of things, from tuck-shop items to a day-trip
away from the hospital. Her "work," which began with the very basic
task of being toilet trained and was rewarded with the very basic reinforcement
of food, becomes (as she is able to cope with it) gradually more
socially demanding,
and is rewarded with gradually less immediate and less-tangible rewards: poker
chips rather than food; social approval and encouragement rather than
cigarettes.
In this way, her once-vegetable-like existence is replaced by a life
of at least
relative social usefulness and the prospect of a return to the
outside world.
A final example: a difficult child in a school-room situation is
constantly disrupting
the class by jumping up and speaking out of turn. The teacher (who
has just arrived
back from a summer course on applied behavior analysis and behavior
modification)
stops scolding him each time he does this and simply ignores him, counselling
the other children to do the same. If he gets too disruptive, she may
calmly and
without fanfare isolate him from the others for a few minutes. At the
same time,
she lavishly praises him whenever he does put his hand up to speak,
or even appear
to be moving towards such a response. Meanwhile, she is keeping careful records
on a graph of the number of times per day that he speaks out of turn
and the number
of times he puts his hand up first. Within a couple of weeks, the
child has stopped
disrupting the class and patiently waits to have his upraised hand
recognized.
Standard Working Principles
These are fairly typical case-studies from the broad range of behavior problems
which have responded to behavior modification techniques. What are the working
principles which unify all three examples? In fact, the ground-rules
are neither
complicated to understand nor difficult to apply. Indeed, behavior modification
programs have won a large following in part precisely because their principles
need not always be put into practice by highly-trained specialists, but can be
easily learned by parents, teachers, ward-attendants and other
non-psychologists
with a minimum of direction from a specialist in the field. The basic working principles
(in which you will see clear remnants of ontological behaviorism) are
as follows:
1. Identify precisely the behavior you wish to change.
Make sure that it is clearly describable in terms of outward
behavior (e.g., "defecating on the floor"; "taking off
his clothes
in public"; "speaking out of turn in the classroom").
Do not give
into the temptation to appeal to "inner states of mind" when dealing
with the behavior problem (e.g., by saying "he's insecure";
"he's
lonely"; "he's jealous," etc.). Stick to the external behavioral
activity which you wish to change. At the same time, do not make any
assumptions
about the child's or adult's innate capacities for learning. Do not
say "He's
schizophrenic, so he'll never be able to eat with a knife and
fork," or "She's
retarded, so she'll never be able to read." If (as the
ontological behaviorist
maintains) behavior is largely, if not totally, controlled by
environmental conditions,
then it follows that we should be able to teach just about anyone to
do just about
anything, provided we discover how to structure the environmental
conditions the
right way. The business of "discovering how to structure the environmental
conditions the right way" is precisely the specialized task of
the behavior
modifier, but the applying of those conditions, once discovered, can be done by
any reasonably intelligent lay person.
2. Try to identify the "reinforcers" (or rewards) which
have been maintaining
that activity. Often these may be surprising, and contrary to your
naive intuitions:
for example, in all three cases mentioned above, undesirable behavior was being
reinforced by "attention" (from parents, ward attendants,
teacher, fellow
students, etc.). The schizophrenic woman's entire bizarre life-style was being
reinforced by the custodial care she received day after day regardless of how
she behaved.
3. Before trying to intervene and change the undesirable behavior, keep a log
of its frequency for several weeks: At what times of day, in what situations,
and how regularly does it occur? Only if you have a record of this
"baseline"
behavior will you be able to affirm, later on, that your behavior modification
strategy has worked. This log is also continued throughout the entire behavior
modification process.
4. To actually modify the undesirable behavior, two processes must go
on at once:
(a) systematically ignore (i.e., fail to reinforce) each instance of
the undesired
behavior at the same time as you (b) reinforce or reward each instance of the
desired behavior. Some elaboration is needed here: first of all, with regard to
(a), most behavior modifiers (drawing on the results of laboratory
research with
animals) maintain that it is better to ignore (or "extinguish
through non-reinforcement")
undesired behavior than to actually punish it. This is because punishment does
not so much suppress the behavior as it simply motivates escape from
the punishing
circumstances. Thus, the undesired behavior may persist, but merely
be transferred
to circumstances where punishment is not forthcoming. Actual punishment is also
eschewed because (as in the case of the disruptive school-child) it
may actually
be functioning as a kind of
We need to examine the track-record of applied behaviorism separately, trying to distinguish those components which a Christian may feel at ease in using from those towards which he should turn a skeptical eye.
twisted reward: negative attention is better than no attention at
all! Secondly,
with regard to (b), the reinforcement of the desired behavior should take place
promptly after each occurrence (at least in the preliminary stages) and, where
the state of the person permits, be accompanied by an explanation that clearly
links the reward to the new behavior (e.g., "I gave you that toy because
you put your hand up so nicely."). Finally, the process of
determining "what
constitutes a reward, or a reinforcer?" is a very individual
one, qualified
by the old dictum that one man's meat is another man's poison. Most people with
biologically-normal bodies are reinforced by food - provided they are hungry -
but beyond that, the would-be behavior modifier must simply discover what sorts
of things are peculiarly rewarding to his client, easy to administer,
not overlycostly,
and not easy for the client to obtain elsewhere. Once this is done, the desired
behavior should become more and more frequent as it is systematically rewarded,
and the undesired behavior should disappear, or "extinguish," as it
consistently fails to be rewarded anymore.
5. During the preliminary (or "acquisition") phase of the
new, desired
behavior, it will need to be reinforced upon each occurrence of the behavior.
Additionally, one may have to begin by rewarding not the full-blown behavioral
response, but rather begin by rewarding anything that resembles a
"try"
or an "approximation" to the behavior, gradually requiring a closer
approximation to the final behavior before the reinforcement is given. However,
once the behavior reliably occurs, it can be maintained thereafter on
intermittent
reinforcement - that is, reinforcement given only occasionally.
Laboratory research
in operant conditioning seems to show that once a behavior is established, it
is in fact better not to reward it after each occurrence; otherwise,
if for some
reason the constant reward suddenly ceases, the newlylearned behavior will also
cease, whereas behavior which is only intermittently reinforced is
very "resistent
to extinction"; it will even persist long after all rewards have
been totally
withdrawn.
6. As a final point, a distinction needs to be made between "primary"
and "secondary" reinforcers. Primary reinforcers are said
by behaviorists
to be those rewards to which an organism "naturally" responds (if it
is biologically normal): food during a state of hunger, water when
thirsty, sleep
when fatigued, sexual release during a state of sexual tension - these are all
primary reinforcers to which we are largely "pre-wired" to
respond and
for which we do not normally have to acquire a taste. Secondary reinforcers
(and we will have reason to question these definitions a little later) are said
to be those acquired through association with primary reinforcers.
Thus, to return
to a practical illustration, the autistic child may begin by learning to make
sounds only for a food reward. But if that food reward (a primary reinforcer)
is always accompanied by the presence of his mother and her delighted
praise over
his accomplishment, then "mother's presence" and
"mother's praise"
become secondary reinforcers for which the child will eventually work
regardless
of whether they are accompanied by the more primary ones.
Since would-be behavior modifiers rarely want to follow around their
clients popping
food rewards into their mouths indefinitely, they tend to try to
"wean"
them from primary to more secondary reinforcers as quickly as
possible. This means
that even while primary reinforcers are the standard rewards, they
are accompanied
clearly and consistently by other things which can later act as
secondary or alternative reinforcers. In point of fact, just about anything can become a
secondary reinforcer.
The pokerchip "tokens" given to the mental patients in the casestudy
cited above are a clear example: like ordinary money, they have no
intrinsic value
to the one who possesses them; rather, they acquire their value by
their association
with other, more primary, reinforcers such as food, clothing, cigarettes, and
so forth. But even the setting in which primary reinforcement is
given may become
a secondary reinforcer. Thus the autistic child who has become used to getting
his food rewards (primary reinforcers) in his highchair may soon
perform desired
behaviors simply for the privilege of getting into the highchair
(which has become
a secondary reinforcer by its association with food). The process of
discovering
and exploiting secondary reinforcers is another skill exercised by
the professional
behavior modifier, but one which, once understood, is easily applied by the lay
worker as well.
Applied Behaviorism: What Can Christians Accept?
As we have stated in earlier parts of this essay, ontological, methodological,
and applied behaviorism all have a host of critics,' whose guiding values, if
not Christian, may be humanistic, rationalistic, Marxist or whatever. And so it
is not simply applied behaviorism itself but also its critics which
must be judged
by the standards of biblical revelation. In the absence of thoughtful
reflection
guided by biblical principles, it is all too easy for Christians
either to accept
or reject unconditionally the entire enterprise of applied behaviorism. This is
hardly surprising, since it is our contention that applied
behaviorism is compatible
with certain biblical truths and incompatible with others. The difficulty comes
in distinguishing among these. What follows is a preliminary (and far
from exhaustive)
attempt to do so by discussing three common criticisms of applied
behaviorism.
Criticism 1: "Behavior modification techniques work on the assumption that
man is purely selfish, hedonistic pleasure-seeker motivated to work
only for the
sake of reward. "
This is a criticism which, from a Christian standpoint, is valid if the concept
of "reward" is too narrowly-defined, but invalid if it assumes that
man is intrinsically more self sacrificial than we know him to be on the basis of biblical
revelation. To elaborate,
there is nothing in Scripture which contradicts the notion that even
the redeemed
man is a seeker after rewards: C. S. Lewis (who was otherwise no friend-indeed,
he was a deadly foe-of behaviorism)' points out in his essay, "The Weight
of Glory" that
The New Testament has lots to say about self-denial, but not about self-denial as an end in itself. We are told to deny ourselves and to take up our crosses in order that we may follow Christ (but) nearly every description of what we shall ultimately find if we do so contains an appeal to desire. If there lurks in most modern minds the notion that to desire our own good and earnestly to hope for the enjoyment of it, is a bad thing, I submit that this notion has crept in from Kant and the Stoics and is no part of the Christian faith. Indeed, if we consider the unblushing promises of reward and the staggering nature of the rewards promised in the Gospels, it would seem that Our Lord finds our desires, not too strong, but too weak. We are half-hearted creatures, footing about with drink and sex and ambition when infinite joy is offered us, like an ignorant child who wants to go on making mud pies in a slum because he cannot imagine what is meant by the offer of a holiday at the sea. We are far too easily pleased.5
Lewis is making two very important points here: firstly (on the side
of the behaviorists),
an appeal to "reward" for work done (even the
"work" of learning
a new behavior) is not an intrinsically un-Christian notion. Indeed,
the opposite
assumption-that man at his highest can work in a purely
disinterested, self-sacrificial
manner-although it sounds superficially Christian, is actually a
legacy of optimistic
humanism and not of Christianity at all. Not only does God build the incentive
of ultimate heavenly rewards into the description of the redeemed
life (as Revelation
21 and 22 unashamedly show) but the entire history of His dealings with Israel
indicates clearly that God's people were regularly exposed to His
reward and favor
when they lived by his standards and to his chastisement when they did not. And
if the Creator in His wisdom assumes the need for immediate and
long-range incentives
in us, we are scarcely being un-Christian in assuming like needs in
one another.
Having thus apparently opened the door to the unapologetic use of
behavior modification
techniques by Christian parents and teachers, let me hasten to make a
second very
important qualifying point from Lewis' quote. Lewis points out that "Our
Lord finds our desires not too strong, but too weak;" this leads us to the
very important consideration of what constitutes a "reward"
or reinforcer
in a behavior modification scheme. A little earlier, we spoke of the
behaviorist
distinction between "primary" and "secondary"
reinforcement.
This distinction, in its extreme form, assumes that man's only
"built-in"
motivation is that of physical comfort, and that all other motives (desire for
approval, desire for satisfying work, desire to learn, desire to find
the meaning
of life) are simply derived from the primary incentive to work for
physical comfort.
Such an assumption would hold, for instance, that a child's interst
in religious
matters derives from the fact that his parents reinforce him with "social
approval" for such interest, and that child's capacity to be reinforced by
the parents' social approval in turn derives from the fact that the parents are
the ones who feed, clothe, and protect him. Now it cannot be
emphasized too strongly
that this "hedonistic assumption," about the nature of man is no less
a faith-assumption of ontological behaviorism than the assumptions of determinism, materialism, and "mental processlessness"
with which we dealt earlier. It is an assumption (or hypothesis) which precedes
behaviorist research-not one which has been unequivocally demonstrated by it,
as some seem to believe. While not all applied behaviorists adhere to
this ''hedonistic
assumption," it is part and parcel of ontological behaviorism and as such
constantly creeps into behavior modification schemes when they are applied by
unreflective people or by those who are tempted to see the entire behaviorist
enterprise as some kind of gospel for the solution to all man's problems.
The practical question is not whether Christians should exercise the authority which accompanies whatever office we fill, but the style in which that authority is exercised by the Christian.
What is wrong with such an assumption from a Christian standpoint? After all,
isn't it true that without the basic physical necessities such as
food, shelter,
and sleep nothing else would get done? True, but "is not life
more than food,
and the body more than clothing? 6 If we are made in God's image,
then included
among our most basic motives will be such things as the desire to do creative,
meaningful work,7 the desire for fellowship,8 the desire for "play,"9
and (if we are true to our biblical image of man) none of these can be assumed
to be mere derivatives from the desire for food, shelter, sleep or sex. Indeed,
biblically speaking, the most basic need of all men (if they could
only recognize
it) is not their need for physical survival, but their need for reconciliation
with their Maker. "Thow hast made us for Thyself, and our hearts
are restless
until they find their rest in Thee," wrote Saint Augustine. God Himself is
man's "primary reinforcer," and we forget this scandalous truth only
at our own peril-"for what shall it profit a man if he gain the
whole world,
and lose his soul?"10
So what does all this mean for the judicious use of behavior
modification by Christians?
In practical terms, it means that the physical rewards of food,
candy, cigarettes
and trinkets so over-employed by so many behavior modifiers should not be used
unless it has become abundantly clear that the person is temporarily incapable
of responding to the "higher order" reinforcers such as
social fellowship,
the opportunity for creative work or play, the opportunity to exercise aristic
talents-yes, even the opportunity to worship and learn more about
God. For despite
man's profound and inbuilt ambivalence towards that "ultimate reward"
of reconciliation with God, we should expect to find traces of that
yearning for
God even in emotionally disturbed, autistic, or retarded
children-especially when
they have been claimed by their parents for God's kingdom through
baptism or dedication.11
Even the recent research literature on behavior modification is
beginning to caution
against the naive over-use of tangible, physical rewards in situations where they are not needed.
In one study,
it was shown that children who originally showed a spontaneous
interest in coloring
activities tended to stop doing so after they had been systematically rewarded
with a gold ribbon for being "good colorers." They had, it
was concluded,
been transformed from happy amateurs who colored for the sake of coloring into
mercenary professionals who now required tangible rewards for the exercise of
their talents. The research report concludes with a warning against the use of
"extrinsic rewards'' in situations where it is clear that
''intrinsic rewards"
(such as satisfaction in the mere doing of the activity) are already
at work.12
Christians can welcome this developing recognition among behavior
modifiers that
their original notions about ''rewards" were far too simplistic-but they
should be warned that there often still exists a tendency to resort
to primitive
physical rewards as the "easy way out." We know of this temptation in
our own lives as parents: it's easier to give the child a cookie when
he scrapes
his knee than to take the time to comfort him or read him a story.
And the cookie
"works"-at least in the short run. So do cigarettes and candies when
used as reinforcers for learning new behaviors-but do we really want
the wholesale
addictions to sugar and nicotine which can be the long-term results?
It is ironic
that the behavior modification community includes both those who routinely use
cigarettes and candy as reinforcers for new behaviors and those who, for a fee,
will help you to eliminate your nicotine and calorie dependencies through the
use of behavior modification techniques! Beware, therefore, lest an
over-reliance
on primitive, lower-order reinforcers turn you into someone who is educating a
child or adult for dependence rather that for responsible freedom-into someone
who more resembles a drug-pusher than a true teacher.
Criticism 2: "The practice of Behavior modification divides
people into two
classes: the 'controllers,' who know and practice the system and the
'controlled'
who must submit in passive, ignorant helplessness. This then opens the door to
authoritarian, totalitarian regimes."
Like the first criticism we considered, this second one is both valid
and invalid,
Christianly speaking, depending on certain other considerations. It is invalid
if it assumes that there is something intrinsically wrong with the
existence and
exercise of authority and the capacity for control which accompanies
that authority.
But it is valid inasmuch as it reflects a concern about the potential
for exercising
control in a powerhungry fashion with no acknowledgement of accountability for
the way it is used. Again, let us elaborate both qualifactions of
this criticism.
Catholic theologian Michael Novak, in a recent essay on
behaviorism13 comments
that "there is a widespread belief, in this Protestant (sic) nation, that
Christianity is a religion of individualism, each man his own priest and pope,
each conscience inviolable, each person a potential source of
autonomy and dissent."
Novak then goes on to point out that this concept of man as a free, autonomous
being answerable only to himself and perfectly justified in resisting any and
all attempts at control is a legacy of the Enlightenment, and not of
Christianity
at all (however much the church has been mistakenly tainted by this
teaching.)
Three critical factors tell against the model of Christianity as individualism:
the teachings of the scriptures; the practice of early Christianity,
and the actualities
of Christian life. The reaction against an exaggerated and errant (although in
some ways helpful) emphasis on individualism has been well under way
for several
decades .... Professor Skinner's emphasis on the social character of
human existence
is thus, from a theological point of view, confirmatory of a well-established
trend)14
Hence legitimate authority in the context of community is not to be
confused with
authoritarianism, and Christians are to listen to the voice of Scripture, not
to the drumbeat of secular humanism, in deciding what circumscribes
the exercise
of control in applied behaviorism. The biblical view of man and society clearly
includes authority structuresparents over children, husbands over
wives, the state
over its citizens, the judge over the criminal, the church elders
over the congregation-and
for this reason Christians need not reject applied behaviorism on the alltoo-popular
grounds that it smacks of "control" and that "control of anyone
by anyone else is always intrinsically bad." It isn't. Indeed, according
to Scripture, the fruit of rebellion against legitimate authority is not sweet
tolerance and freedom but chaotic and ugly self-seeking (as the book of Judges
vividly testifies in documenting an era when "each man did what was right
in his own eyes"15). Only a naively optimistic view about the
perfectibility
of man holds otherwise.
Again, lest I appear to be opening the door to the very excercise of despotism
so feared by the secular critics of applied behaviorism, let me
qualify the above
remarks. The critics of behaviorism do well to be concerned about the misuse of
behavioral technology in the hands of the unscrupulous-or even simply
in the hands
of those who trust too naively in the claims of the system. Observing
the trends
in British government, law, and social science in the post-war
period, C.S. Lewis
took up his pen at almost the same time Skinner was writing Walden II and
produced
an anti-behaviorist fantasy novel called That Hideous Strength.16 In this
novel too, science has been given a blank check (this time by the government of
a country rather than an experimental community) to perfect man and
further harness
the powers of nature. Here too, an elite of specialists works for the supposed
greater good of mankind. The difference between Walden II and Belbury
(the scientific
think-tank of Lewis' novel) is that the planners in the latter
situation, through
willful misuse of their power, through sheer ignorance of their own
limitations,
or a combination of both, degenerate into a dog-eat-dog competition
for control.
This competition eventually ends in the destruction of the entire institution
and the merciful restoration of normal life to the surrounding area,
whose people
and resources had been appropriated and manipulated in the name of
progress. Lewis'
novel is, of course, no less a work of fiction than Skinner's, and his negative
version of the results of a scientifically-planned society no less speculative
than Skinner's positive one. To support his case for the finiteness
and depravity
of man, he appeals to the evidence of history and of Scripture, while Skinner
appeals to the past achievements of science and the present successes
of behavior
modification as evidence that man can not only plan his own destiny, but do so
without necessarily abusing the accompanying power. Adherence to
either position
takes the reader beyond evidence to basic faith-assumptions about
man's capacity
for unlimited progress and goodness.
How, then, are Christians to walk the fine line between legitimate exercise of
authority and sinful degeneration into despotic authoritarianism? We
are not guaranteed
immunity from the temptation to assume selfish power in a way that is being so
consistently role-modelled for us in the twentieth century
industrialized world.
However, a few reminders from the scriptural comments about authority may be of
help.
Whatever authority a Christian exercises in the offices of parent,
teacher, husband,
employer, or governor is never self-generated, but is derived from God Himself,
accountable to Him, and therefore to be exercised with an awe verging
on fear and
trembling. Our office is not accorded to us because of any intrinsic merit: we
are as fallen and prone to sin as those under our command. And so the apostle
Paul, even as he admonishes children to obey their parents and servants their
masters, promptly warns those same parents and masters not to abuse
their authority
"knowing that both their Master and yours is in heaven, and
there is no partiality
with Him."17 The practical question is not whether Christians should
exercise the authority which accompanies whatever office we fill-be it parent,
teacher or whatever. Let me rather suggest four important questions regarding
the style in which that authority-and its accompanying power to
dispense rewards
and punishments-is exercised by the Christian.
Firstly, in what spirit are you exercising control? Are you trying to
change the
person's behavior in order to indulge your own desire for power? Are
you exercising
control to compensate for the frustration of being controlled by other people
or other circumstances, pecking order fashion? Are you putting on a
show of authority
to cover up your own uncertainties about the situation? Are you merely trying
to tailor the other person's behavior to fit your peculiar needs and
idiosyncrasies?
None of these, I submit, are valid motives for resorting to the powerful tools
of behavior modification. Ontological behaviorism may insist that the existence
of such motives (being irrelevant internal mental processes) makes no
difference
whatsoever to the effectiveness of a behavior modification
program-but such thinking
must be resolutely rejected. Just as God discerns and judges the spirit behind
an action, so do those over whom we exercise authority-and that
spirit makes all
the difference in the world as to the effectiveness of our program. In the long
run, only when fueled by a sincere and unselfish desire for the
other's good will
any attempt at behavioral control succeed. Again, this is a truth that is being
brought home to applied behaviorists by the realities of their
accumulating professional
experience. The architect of one behavior modification project with difficult
children in a California school system has concluded that
sincerity is an integral part of instruction in behaviorial engineering
The teachers working with (me) on the experiment have sometimes doubted each other's sincerity. One person compliments another, who says 'You're just reinforcing me!' And the response is 'Oh, the hell I am! I really mean it!' With the kids and the staff, we've had to continually stress being sincere. You should really want the other person to change.18
Secondly, for what are you exercising control? Is your
long-term goal the training of an equal, fellow-member of the Body of
Christ-someone
who may well at some future time be in a position of responsible authority over you,
circumstances and gifts
permitting? Or are you, consciously or unconsciously, playing the role of the
animal-trainer, educating for a more and more total dependence on yourself? If
the latter, then beware! You are not God; any sovereignty you have
over the life
of another exists only to direct that other to the true Master of us
all. We are
called to be willing bond slaves of Jesus Christ and Him alone: deference to all
other legitimate authority is the by-product of obedience to Him, and
cannot-indeed,
dare not exist on its own.
Thirdly, how independently are you exercising behavioral control? As
Christians,
we are given the gifts of prayer, Scripture, and the counsel of
fellow-believers
as safeguards against our sinful tendency to distort reality. Is the
use of behavioral
techniques being subjected to these three courts of appeal for
endorsement, modification,
or outright rejection? In particular I would stress the
responsibility of believing
bodies of Christians not to be intimidated by the scientistic
trappings of behaviorism:
it is for us to hold applied behaviorism accountable to the standards
of the Word,
and not vice-versa.
Finally, how hastily are you resorting to the techniques of behavioral control?
A recent reviewer of the behavior modification scene reported suprise when one
of the most prestigious pioneers of behavior modification introduced
a token-reinforcement
system into a highly disruptive seventh-grade class "only as a last resort
after more traditional methods had failed to end the chaos, When I asked why,
he replied, 'Why use tokens when something else will work?19
If a non-Christian
specialist in applied behaviorism employs his tools only as a last resort, we
would do well to ask ourselves why. I suspect that the emerging cautiousness of
such practitioners reflects their growing awareness that learning is not simply
a matter of tangible rewards and punishments, however much of these
do enter into
the picture. Indeed, a constant reliance on such rewards and
punishments may simply
cause the child to regress to notions of primitive reciprocity
("you scratch
my back and I'll scratch yours") in his dealing with others when, in fact,
his behavior was already quite amenable to change based on an appeal to reason,
emotion, religious conviction or a combination of all three.
Ontological behaviorism
does not make room for the possibility that children may pass through definite
stages in their social, intellectual, and moral development (with a rewards-and
punishments
orientation a legitimate, but very immature phase in that development).20 Rather it assumes that the stimulus-response laws of respondent and
operant conditioning
are the sole vehicle of learning for all organisms (animal or human, normal or
abnormal) at all ages and stages of life. But the truth of the matter is that
we know far too little about the degree to which these techniques
pioneered almost
exclusively on animals and "marginal" human beings-such as retardates
and severely disturbed persons are applicable without substantial qualification
to persons leading ordinary lives in ordinary homes, classrooms and workplaces.
The track record of applied behaviorism increasingly suggests that a
healthy skepticism
is warranted.
Criticism 3: "By locating all causes for behavior change in the
environment,
behavior modification programs deny, or at least ignore, the existence of free
will, and hence assign human beings no credit for their accomplishments and no
blame for their misdeeds."
This final criticism to which this paper addresses itself is a rather complex
argument to handle from a Christian point of view, given the
theological differences
which have historically existed within the church regarding the part played by
man's will in the process of both Salvation and Sanctification. But I
am personally
inclined to agree with Novak,21 when he maintains that the thrust of Scripture
is such as to give man no credit for anything good he does (all such goodness
being rooted in the grace of God), but, on the other hand, to hold him (but for
the work of Christ) fully responsible for his sinful deeds even while
acknowledging
that such sin is not merely personal because the entire creation has
been flawed
by man's fall and is never totally supportive of good actions. This is one of
the apparent paradoxes of Scripture which is hardly amenable to analysis by the
fragile tools of human logic-but even so, it does shed light on two
issues regarding
the Christian's attitude to applied behaviorism: firstly, if the source of our
goodness lies outside ourselves, then we need not reject applied
behaviorism merely
on the grounds that it denies man due "credit" for his good
deeds. True,
behaviorism errs in citing not God, but the environment as the ultimate source
of man's accomplishments; but the opposite position whereby man
himself is exalted
as the autonomous source of all noble actions is simply another legacy of the
humanistic rejection of God and His replacement by so-called autonomous man as
the center of the universe. Hence we can agree with Novak when he
supports Skinner
to the extent of saying "at no point is man's autonomy such that
he can take
credit for it. Such as it is, it has been given to him, both in its
abiding tendencies
and in its actual exercise. It is 'grace' or 'gift,' rather than his
own creation,"
although as a Christian he then parts ways with Skinner in affirming that the
ultimate source of that gift is in God and not (or only secondarily)
in the impersonal
pressures of the environment. "Hence," (he concludes) 'theonomy"
rather that 'autonomy' is a more accurate name for the human
reality."22
On the other hand (and this is my second point) if the source of our
badness lies
essentially within ourselves, and we are answerable for it, then the Christian
and behaviorist views of justice must diverge quite radically from one another.
For it will be recalled that, according to strict ontological
behaviorism, man's
behavior (aside from certain genetically-programmed dispositions) is
totally determined
by the events of his environment and that for this reason both personal freedom
and the personal credit (i.e., "dignity") resulting from
our accomplishments
are illustory. By the same reasoning, however, the notions of
personal responsibility
and accountability are also illustory: if my enviroment is to be credited with
my achievements, it must also take the blame for my mistakes and misdeeds. This
leads to a philosophy of justice according to which law-breakers are regarded
not as responsible agents who have willingly and knowingly violated
certain standards
of conduct, but as persons whose misdeeds should either be entirely overlooked
("Poor fellow-he's just a victim of his past!") or at most treated as
"illnesses" needing to be "cured," rather than as
"sins"
needing to be "punished." At first glance, this seems like
a very enlightened
attitude; but in point of fact, its practical application results all too often
in one of two opposite abuses: either the victimization of society at large or
(paradoxical as it may seem) of the criminal himself.
If the Source of our badness lies essentially within ourselves, and we are answerable for it, then the Christian and behaviorist views of justice must diverge quite radically from one another.
With regard to the first abuse, the growing tendency to regard the criminal as
"more sinned against (by his environment) than sinning" appears to be
generating a state of increasing judicial anarchy in the western world. Reduced
or suspended sentences have become increasingly the norm even for what used to
be regarded as serious crimes-with no accompanying evidence that this attitude
of sympathy and leniency has in any way reduced the likelihood that
the criminal
will repeat his offence." In the traditional system of criminal law,
....vengeance and retribution were recognized as important threads of the social fabric, not because they deterred or reformed the offender, but because they reasurred and satisfied the offended. This was not the satisfaction of some dark animal need. Citizens entered into the social contract with the understanding that society would guarantee-or at least put a premium on-their lives, dignity, and the right to enjoy their possessions. It was only when retribution followed injury that citizens could be reassured and satisfied that society really did place some value on other persons. This wasand is-a central need for any society. And, just as excessive or unjust punishment brutalizes the offender because it suggests that he is of no value, insufficient punishment brutalizes the victim for the same reason24
These are not words written by a Christian journalist-but we can echo
her sentiments
when we recall that Romans 13 speaks of the civil government (whether
she realizes
this fact or not) as being "God's servant for your good. .
.(and) the servant
of God to execute his (i.e., God's) wrath on the wrongdoer."
But one result of the ascendency of a behaviorist view of crime has
been the unquestioned
assumption that it is only environments, not people, that can be held
accountable
for crime. Consequently, the state whose penal system rests on such
an assumption
may violate the biblical imperative in two serious ways: In the first place, it
assumes that persons are not born prone to evil, but are merely tabulae rasae
("blank slates") on which the environment alone writes the program of
our subsequent behavioral tendencies. By this reckoning, crime is totally the
outcome of poverty or deprived social conditions-although this, (continues the
same journalist)
does not explain why the overwhelming majority of poor Canadians do not commit crimes, nor why so many well-off ones do, (nor why), during the 1950's- 1970's when Canadians were enjoying rapidly im
proving standards of living and social services unequalled in any other period of history, the crime rates-instead of going downwere rapidly going up,25
In the second place, in refusing to exercise its retributive mandate
against the
wrongdoer, the behaviorist-leaning penal system, and the state which condones
it, have failed to strike the balance between justice and mercy
demanded by biblical
norms for society.
Regardless of whether punishment deters or rehabilitates, it is necessary for justice .... Cynicism and callous indifference to good and evil are the products of a society that, like ours, is less concerned with the needs of those who observe its rules than with those who break them.26
If journalists of the secular press-without the privilege of biblical faith or
literacy-are, on the basis of the observed chaos in criminal justice, appealing
for a return to a more biblical view of crime and punishment, it
should give thinking
Christians much cause for reflection on the type of government they
wish to support
in the future.
But the victimization of society by criminals held inadequately responsible for
their actions is only one result of adherence to an environmental determinist
view of behavior. The other, strange as it may seem, concerns the
likelihood that
the criminal himself will be unjustly victimized. For it is not always the case
that behavioristinfluenced penal systems end up doing nothing to the criminal,
on the grounds that his crime is "really his environment's
fault, not his."
It is just as likely that such a theory of criminal treatment may
very well acknowledge
that the offender's environment has indeed disposed him towards
continuous wrong-doing
and that he therefore merits the privilege of re-education at the
state's expense.
C. S. Lewis was prophetically sensitive to the hidden potential for injustice
inherent in such a view when the jargon of criminal
"rehabilitation'' first
began to replace the traditional notion of "retribution" in the minds
of penologists a quarter of a century ago. According to this newly-fashionable
theory (Lewis called it ''The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment"), when a
criminal himself is held responsible for his crime and punished accordingly, he
is being victimized by a barbarous and unenlighteded spirit of revenge, whereas
when he is exposed rather to "treatment," "rehabilitation,"
or "reeducation," he is being treated in an enlightened and
scientific
manner which is kinder to the criminal and also promotes the goals of
future crime-deterrence.
"Thus," (in changing from retributive to a behaviorist
theory of penology)
"it appears at first sight that we have passed from the harsh
and self-righteous
notion of giving the wicked their deserts to the charitable and enlightened one
of tending the psychologically sick."27 But, Lewis goes on to say, let
us not be fooled by a change in terminology:
the things done to the criminal, even if they are called cures, will be just as compulsory as they were in the old days when we called them punishments. If a tendency to steal can be cured by psychotherapy, the thief will no doubt be forced to undergo the treatment.28
Even worse, Lewis warned, once a person passes from the category of
"morally
wrong" to the category of "psychologically sick, " then there is
an accompanying loss of precision both in the definition of what is
"sick"
and the definition of what constitutes adequate
"treatment." Seriously
"sick " people, having no specialized knowledge themselves
of medicine,
must necessarily trust their doctors to know both that they really are sick,
and what and how long it will take to treat them. The traditional
concept of "deserved"
punishment was rooted in the notion that not just a specialized elite, but that
all adults capable of functioning in society were able to distinguish between
lawful and unlawful acts. Once we concede that people passively
"catch"
bad behavior from their environment in the same way they
"catch" measles
or bubonic plague, then it is up to the specialists both to diagnose the disease
and prescribe the cure. In extreme cases, the sick person can be
quarantined indefinitely
for his own good and the good of society, whether he likes it or not. Hence an
additional danger of a behaviorist-rooted theory of penology is that
the definite
sentence for a definite type of crime, to which traditional
jurisprudence adhered,
may be replaced by an indefinite sentence which can be lengthened or shortened
at the discretion of the psychological "experts."
A further danger is that, having conceded to specialists their superior wisdom
in defining what is "criminally sick," we may find ourselves, under
an unscrupulous political regime, being labelled "sick" and forced to
undergo "treatment" for any opinion or practice that is
deemed threatening
to the status quo.
We know that one school of psychology already regards religion as a neurosis. When this particular neurosis becomes inconvenient so government, what is to hinder government from proceeding to 'cure' it? . . And thus when the command is given, every prominent Christian in the land may vanish overnight into Institutions for the treatment of the ideologically unsound, and it will rest with the expert gaolers to say when (if ever) they are to re-emerge. But it will not be persecution. Even if the treatment is painful, even if it is life long, even if it is fatal, that will only be a regrettable accident; the intention was purely therapeutic. In ordinary medicine, there were painful operations and fatal operations; so in this. But because they are 'treatment,' not punishment, they can be criticized only by fellow experts and on technical grounds, never by men as men and on grounds of justice.29
Eager to assimilate and apply these "progressive" concepts of prison reform, the Britain of the early 50's would give Lewis no hearing for his arguments (he finally published them in an Australian legal journal.) It was only a little later, however, that the first reports of so called brainwashing procedures began to leak out of China. A recent Skinnerian critic writes:
When China began industrialization, it adopted procedures much like those described in Beyond Freedom and Dignsty. It often applied reinforcement rather than aversive methods to induce its people to accept the new behavioral environment. It then arranged its reward system so as to positively reinforce actions that were in conformity with the values of the new environment. Deviation was not so much punished as it was treated. Recalcitrant individuals were given group-think treatments-called brain-washing-in which they were rewarded for expressing approved sentiments.30
The judicious arrangement of reinforcers in the outside environment has now been buttressed by the use of drugs to alter-or at least render innocuous the internal minds of dissidents in Russia, as Solzhenitsyn and others have reported. And lest we be tempted to think that such abuses (naive or deliberate) could "never happen here," it needs to be pointed out that in California (unquestionably the most eager state in the union when it comes to employing the latest ideas from psychology and the personnel to implement them), since the introduction of rehabilitative, behavior modification types of prison programs in the fifties, "the median term served by 'felony first releases' has risen from twenty to thirty-six months-twice the national average."31 This strongly suggests the materialization of Lewis' fears of "indefinite sentencing." Reports from prisons in other parts of the country where behavior modification programs are in use stress repeatedly that prisoners would "rather have remained in solitary confinement"32 than take part. A typical program consists of several differenct "levels" of privileges that the prisoner must attain by displaying the right behavior, which is rewarded by the distribution of token-points by guards and psychiatric staff
on their own arbitrary discretion. . . Inmates are awarded tokens for proper responses to guards, such as 'Good morning sir? how are you, sir? Yes, sir,' etc . . . . (During group therapy, the prisoner's therapist) will point out what problems as inmate has, and, whether they're real or not, that inmate is required to solve his problem in the group. If the inmate doesn't try to solve this problem forced on him, then he's not cooperating with the behavior modification program, which results in a hard way to go on all fronts. One way in which an inmate is harassed is in receiving less tokens per day. Since tokens are given out by state employed personnel at their own discretion, an inmate could find himself in a tight situation if he starts receiving just enough tokens for everyday necessities and nothing else .... if one doesn't have enough tokens to pay rent, one is simply thrown (down to a lower level) for a period of time.33
In this program, too, the uncertainty of indefinite sentencing is routine:
It usually takes a six-month period for one who is cooperating with the behavior modification program to complete it and be transferred out. However, with this arbitrary means of distributing tokens, and in the name of therapy, an inmate can be forced to remain (in the program) until the maximum of his sentence is up.
These anecdotal reports come to us from individual inmates who, it
can be argued,
are hardly supplying us with careful documentation and may, in
addition, be prone
to exaggeration. But confirmation of the agonies of
"indeterminate sentencing"
comes from another, more articulate source-one who might be expected to support
the status quo of the prison system, not oppose it: Charles Colson was a crack
Washington lawyer and Richard Nixon's top aide who, in the wake of
his conversion
to Christianity decided to plead guilty to certain Watergateconnected offenses
and take no privileges for the duration of his prison sentence. Now
working full
time in the cause of prison reform, he writes in his
recently-published autobiography,
that one of the most agonizing aspects of prison life is the guessing
game which
all inmates must constantly play with regard to the probability of
being paroled
or not at their next hearing-a probability which appears to be almost totally
determined by the caprice of an overworked, underinformed committee.34
One is also reminded of the question, raised in an earlier part of this essay,
as to whether or not environmental manipulation of behavior can work
at all effectively
if the target of that manipulation is a human being who knows, or has guessed,
the nature of those manipulations and simply decided that he does not
agree with
their goals. Again, the first-hand reports of prisoners in behavior
modification
programs would suggest not: "The guards put on a front of
politeness, concern,
and friendship. I had had enough of the cells, guards, and phoniness those few
hours between the 6th and 7th of April and refused to eat or talk to
anyone."
Fellow inmates co-operating with the program are regarded no less
cynically: they
are
brain-washed inmates . . . stool pigeons, snitches, puppets, and serve the purpose of carrying out the personnel's wishes to a fuller degree. These inmates set 'examples' for the newer block residents, advocate block policy, and of course keep the personnel up on all the activities of inmates whom officials are keeping a close eye on, and especially those inmates who are in opposition to the program.35
In light of such comments, Lewis' words of two and one half decades ago ring particularly prophetic:
To undergo all those assaults on my personality which modern psycho therapy knows how to deliver; to he taken without consent from my home and friends; to lose my liberty; to be remade after some pattern of normality' hatched in a Viennese (or Harvardian?)36 laboratory to which I never professed allegiance; to know that this process will never end until either my captors have succeeded or I grow wise enough to cheat them with apparent success-who cares whether this is called Punishment or not? That it includes most of the elements for which any punishment is feared-shame, exile, bondage, and years eaten by the locust-is obvious. Only enormous ill-desert could justify it; but ill-desert is the very conception which the Humanitarian theory has thrown overboard37
This lengthy discussion of the potential for abuse inherent in applied behaviorism-abuse
of the rights of the law-abiding majority, but also of the
crime-performing minority-is
intended to emphasize the fact that Christian responsibility for the
uses of these
techniques extends beyond the confines of our individual lives as the parents
and teachers of children and into the very bedrock of our society and
the social
consequences of its policies. We are living with the legacy of
several centuries
of combined belief in the "science ideal" (the notion that the entire
universe is impersonal and mechanistic) and the "freedom ideal" (the
notion that man, on his own can somehow transcend his own determinism and play
God)-and both ontological and applied behaviorism are part and parcel of this
legacy. Change will not come easily-partly because of the
longstanding and pervasive
nature of this "alternative religion," but also partly because, for
all its errors, it is not totally lacking in elements of biblical truth, as I
have tried to indicate. This makes the business of separating wheat from chaff
one which requires all of the wisdom that the Holy Spirit can give to us, both
as individuals and as interdependent members of the one Body of Christ. It also
renders very challenging the business of deciding under what circumstances we
should or should not support the schemes of applied behaviorism, and (just as
important) the process of articulating clearly, forcefully-and if
necessary, sacrificially-our
reasons for taking either of these stands at a particular time. This
trio of articles
has been a preliminary attempt to provide some Christian guidelines
to that end.
REFERENCES
1Some standard works which discuss ease studies and principles of
behavior modification
include
a) Allyon, T. and Azrin, N. The Token Economy: A Motivational
System for Therapy and Rehabilitation. New York: Appleton-CenturyCrofts, 1968.
b) Honig W.K. (Ed.) Operant Behavior: Areas of Research and Application. New York:
Appteton-Century-Crofts, 1966,
e)Wolpe, J. The Practice of Behavior Therapy. New York; Pergamon, 1969.
2See particularly, Wheeler, H. (Ed.) Beyond the Punitive Society, San
Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company, 1973.
3A criticism repeatedly levelled by Noam Chomsky. See his essay
''Psychology and
Ideology" in his anthology For Reasons of State. New York: Random House,
1973.
4To the best of my knowledge, Lewis never tackled behaviorism by that name and
probably was not even in touch with the actual psychology literature on it. But
his aversion to a behaviorist world-view is clear in his novel That
Hideous Strength
(London: John Lane the Bodley Head Ltd., 1945), his essay "The
Humanitarian
Theory of Punishment" (1949; reprinted in God in the Dock, Grand Rapids:
Eerdmans, 1970), and his Abolition of Man, London: Wm. Collins & Sons Ltd.,
1943.
5The Weight of Glory," in a collection by the same title.
Grand Rapids, Eerdmans, 1965
6 Matt. 6:25
7cf. Genesis 1-2
8As implied in the triune nature of God and the "Body" analogy of the
church which Paul develops in 1 Cor. 12 and Eph. 4.
9Psalm 104:26
10Mark 6:25
11Dale Evans Rogers' Angel Unaware and Brother Andrew's God's
Smuggler both contain heartwarming accounts of the spontaneous
religious impulse
in retarded children.
12Greene, 0. and Lepper, MR. "How to Turn Play Into
Work." Psychology Today, September, 1974, pp. 49-54.
13Novak, M. "Is He Really a Grand Inquisitor?" in Wheeler, Op. Cit.
pp. 230-246.
14ibid., p.232.
15Judges 17:6, 21:25
16Lewis, CS. That Hideous Strength. London: John Lane the Bodley Head Ltd.,
1945.
17Ephesians 6:19
18Gray, F., Granbard, P.S., and Rosenberg, H. "Little
Brother is Changing
You." Psychology Today, March 1974, pp. 42-46.
19Goodall, K. "Shapers at Work." Psychology Today,
November, 1972.
pp. 53-62, 132-13g.
20See particularly the writings of Jean Piaget and Lawrence Kohtberg for an
elaboration of this position.
21Novak, M. Op. Cit., p.233.
221bid., p. 234.
23Amiel, B. "The Chaos of Criminal Justice in Canada." Saturday
Night,
Sept. 1975, 19-25.
24Ibid.
25ibid.
26Ibid.
27Lewis, CS. "The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment," in God in
the
Dock Grand Rapids: Eerdmnns, 1970.
28Ibid.
29Ibid.
30Wheeler, H. "A Non-Punitive World?" in Wheeler, H.
(Ed.) Op. Cit.,
p. 19.
31Babbage, SB. "CS. Lewis and the humanitarian theory of punishment"
Christian Scholar's Review, 1972, 2(3) 234-235.
32Nicholson, W.G. "Michigan intensive program center," R. T.:
A
Journal
of Radical Therapy, 1975, 4(6).
33ibid.
34Colson, C. Born Again. Old Toppan, N.J.: Chosen Books, 1975.
35Nicholson, Op. Cit.
36My parentheses.
37Lewis, CS. "The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment.
ism leaves no room for spiritual realities over and above what is reducible to
the purely physical; "mental processlessness" leaves no
room for activities
such as reasoning, feeling, or creatively imagining - activities which we know
to be characteristic of God himself and therefore (however
imperfectly) of human
beings made in His image. Moreover, we pointed out that ontological
behaviorists
themselves, once they bump up against created reality, cannot
themselves consistently
live up to the assumptions of their position: in one way or another, autonomous
man, morally-accountable man, thinking man, spirituallyoriented man returns to
the behaviorist system which claims to have dispensed with him. This
is a further
reason for questioning the validity of this "new gospel."
However, the serious flaws of ontological behaviorism
129MARY STEWART VAN LEEUWEN
do not alter the fact that the applied techniques of behaviorism are everywhere
around us, are much used, and in many ways apparently "work." Since,
as we have already pointed out, the applied behaviorist does not
necessarily adhere
to behaviorism as a total world view, perhaps we need to examine the
track-record
of applied behaviorism separately, trying to distinguish those components which
a Christian may feel at ease in using from those towards which he should turn
a skeptical eye. We will begin with some typical examples and standard working
principles of behavior modification techniques, then go on to suggest
what Christians
might accept and reject from the system, and why. The following
examples are based
on techniques of operant conditioning exclusively, since it is these techniques
that the lay reader is most apt to see being applied in schools,
clubs, and homes.
The application of respondent conditioning techniques, as described in Part I
of this essay, is still largely restricted to the professional
therapists' office
and to very selective institutional settings.'
Applied Behaviorism: Some Typical Examples
Let us return to Billy, the autistic child whose bizarre, unmanageable behavior
was described at the beginning of Part I of this paper. When I first met Billy,
although I had only a modicum of training in the techniques of
behavior modification
I spent some time showing Billy's parents how certain (essentially
simple) principles
of behavior modification could be used to "shape" socially desirable
actions in their son and at the same time "extinguish" his
bizarre habits:
since he was a good eater, I simply took charge of his food dish while he was
captive in his highchair and made each spoonful contingent on his emitting some
approximation to the word "food." To begin with, I promptly rewarded,
or "reinforced" any chance grunt with a mouthful of food, but as the
child began to make the association between vocalizing and getting
food, I could
begin to require progressively more of him: not just any grunt, but
only an "oo-o"
sound would then be rewarded, and a little later, only an "oo-d" and
finally, only the entire word "food." In less than 10 minutes, Billy
was saying a word, and (just as important) paying close attention to
another human
being. As an amateur behavior modifier, I had made use of essentially the same
principle as animal trainers use to teach circus animals complicated
tricks: one
begins by rewarding remote approximations to the final "trick" - bits
of behavior which the animal is likely to display anyway in the normal course
of its activities, and once these "simple" behaviors can be reliably
elicited by the food treats, the trainer can gradually require more
and more complicated
behavior for the same reward until the tiger is finally waltzing with the bear,
or (a much-quoted example from B.F. Skinner's Harvard laboratory) the pigeons
are playing ping-pong with each other by batting a celluloid ball
back and forth
across a table with their beaks. Of course, the pigeons don't "know"
that they're playing a game called ping-pong, nor did Billy
"know" that
the noises he was emitting constituted a real word in a real language
that could
be used to communicate - but in the case of autistic children like Billy, what
begins as a mere noise emitted to food which cannot be obtained any other way
can gradually be taught to be used as a label, then as part of a
request or question,
and eventually as part of a real (albeit still somewhat mechanistic)
conversation.
130
Another example: a severely regressed schizophrenic woman has been vegetating
on the back ward of a mental hospital for years, unreachable by more
traditional
forms of therapy, spending what time she is not eating or sleeping in
the endless
repetition of bizarre phrases and actions, apparently almost totally oblivious
to the real world around her. Then the hospital institutes a behavior
modification
program. The behavior modifiers point out that, far from helping the woman by
tolerating or even indulging her bizarre behavior, the hospital staff
are effectively
rewarding, or "reinforcing" it, in the first place by giving her food
and shelter while she persists in it, and secondly by paying attention to her
when she engages in it. Suddenly the entire working operation of the
ward changes.
The woman discovers, for instance, that she will not get a meal
until, for example,
she begins to use the toilet for defecation instead of soiling herself. To the
surprise of the skeptical ward attendants (who have been cleaning her
up for years),
she is toilet trained within days. A little later, she is made to
"earn"
yard privileges (or cigarettes, or candy, or whatever she finds
particularly rewarding)
by washing and dressing appropriately. Still later, she learns to
hold a coherent
conversation, or help with tasks around the ward, and
"earns" not direct
rewards, but plastic poker-chips, a sort of "local
currency," with which
she can "buy" a number of things, from tuck-shop items to a day-trip
away from the hospital. Her "work," which began with the very basic
task of being toilettrained and was rewarded with the very basic reinforcement
of food, becomes (as she is able to cope with it) gradually more
socially demanding,
and is rewarded with gradually lessimmediate and less-tangible rewards: poker
chips rather than food; social approval and encouragement rather than
cigarettes.
In this way, her once-vegetable-like existence is replaced by a life
of at least
relative social usefulness and the prospect of a return to the
outside world.
A final example: a difficult child in a school-room situation is
constantly disrupting
the class by jumping up and speaking out of turn. The teacher (who
has just arrived
back from a summer course on applied behavior analysis and behavior
modification)
stops scolding him each time he does this and simply ignores him, counselling
the other children to do the same. If he gets too disruptive, she may
calmly and
without fanfare isolate him from the others for a few minutes. At the
same time,
she lavishly praises him whenever he does put his hand up to speak,
or even appear
to be moving towards such a response. Meanwhile, she is keeping careful records
on a graph of the number of times per day that he speaks out of turn
and the number
of times he puts his hand up first. Within a couple of weeks, the
child has stopped
disrupting the class and patiently waits to have his upraised hand
recognized.
Standard Working Principles
These are fairly typical case-studies from the broad range of behavior problems
which have responded to behavior modification techniques. What are the working
principles which unify all three examples? In fact, the ground-rules
are neither
complicated to understand nor difficult to apply. Indeed, behavior modification
programs have won a large following in part precisely because their principles
need not always be put into practice by highly-trained specialists, but can be
easily learned by parents, teachers, ward-attendants and other
non-psychologists
with a mini
JOURNAL OFTHEAMERICAN SCIENTIFIC AFFILIATION
APPLIED BEHAVIORISM
mum of direction from a specialist in the field. The basic working principles
(in which you will see clear remnants of ontological behaviorism) are
as follows:
1. Identify precisely the behavior you wish to change.
Make sure that it is clearly describable in terms of outward
behavior (e.g., "defecating on the floor"; "taking off
his clothes
in public"; "speaking out of turn in the classroom").
Do not give
into the temptation to appeal to "inner states of mind" when dealing
with the behavior problem (e.g., by saying "he's insecure";
"he's
lonely"; "he's jealous," etc.). Stick to the external behavioral
activity which you wish to change. At the same time, do not make any
assumptions
about the child's or adult's innate capacities for learning. Do not
say "He's
schizophrenic, so he'll never be able to eat with a knife and
fork," or "She's
retarded, so she'll never be able to read." If (as the
ontological behaviorist
maintains) behavior is largely, if not totally, controlled by
environmental conditions,
then it follows that we should be able to teach just about anyone to
do just about
anything, provided we discover how to structure the environmental
conditions the
right way. The business of "discovering how to structure the environmental
conditions the right way" is precisely the specialized task of
the behavior
modifier, but the applying of those conditions, once discovered, can be done by
any reasonably intelligent lay person.
2. Try to identify the "reinforcers" (or rewards) which
have been maintaining
that activity. Often these may be surprising, and contrary to your
naive intuitions:
for example, in all three cases mentioned above, undesirable behavior was being
reinforced by "attention" (from parents, ward attendants,
teacher, fellow
students, etc.). The schizophrenic woman's entire bizarre life-style was being
reinforced by the custodial care she received day after day regardless of how
she behaved.
3. Before trying to intervene and change the undesirable behavior, keep a log
of its frequency for several weeks: At what times of day, in what situations,
and how regularly does it occur? Only if you have a record of this
"baseline"
behavior will you be able to affirm, later on, that your behavior modification
strategy has worked. This log is also continued throughout the entire behavior
modification process.
4. To actually modify the undesirable behavior, two processes must go
on at once:
(a) systematically ignore (i.e., fail to reinforce) each instance of
the undesired
behavior at the same time as you (b) reinforce or reward each instance of the
desired behavior. Some elaboration is needed here: first of all, with regard to
(a), most behavior modifiers (drawing on the results of laboratory
research with
animals) maintain that it is better to ignore (or "extinguish
through non-reinforcement")
undesired behavior than to actually punish it. This is because punishment does
not so much suppress the behavior as it simply motivates escape from
the punishing
circumstances. Thus, the undesired behavior may persist, but merely
be transferred
to circumstances where punishment is not forthcoming. Actual punishment is also
eschewed because (as in the case of the disruptive school-child) it
may actually
be functioning as a kind of
SEPTEMBER 1979
We need to examine the track-record of applied behaviorism separately, trying
to distinguish those components which a Christian may feel at ease in
using from
those towards which he should turn a skeptical eye.
twisted reward: negative attention is better than no attention at
all! Secondly,
with regard to (b), the reinforcement of the desired behavior should take place
promptly after each occurrence (at least in the preliminary stages) and, where
the state of the person permits, be accompanied by an explanation that clearly
links the reward to the new behavior (e.g., "I gave you that toy because
you put your hand up so nicely."). Finally, the process of
determining "what
constitutes a reward, or a reinforcer?" is a very individual
one, qualified
by the old dictum that one man's meat is another man's poison. Most people with
biologically-normal bodies are reinforced by food - provided they are hungry -
but beyond that, the would-be behavior modifier must simply discover what sorts
of things are peculiarly rewarding to his client, easy to administer,
not overlycostly,
and not easy for the client to obtain elsewhere. Once this is done, the desired
behavior should become more and more frequent as it is systematically rewarded,
and the undesired behavior should disappear, or "extinguish," as it
consistently fails to be rewarded anymore.
5. During the preliminary (or "acquisition") phase of the
new, desired
behavior, it will need to be reinforced upon each occurrence of the behavior.
Additionally, one may have to begin by rewarding not the full-blown behavioral
response, but rather begin by rewarding anything that resembles a
"try"
or an "approximation" to the behavior, gradually requiring a closer
approximation to the final behavior before the reinforcement is given. However,
once the behavior reliably occurs, it can be maintained thereafter on
intermittent
reinforcement - that is, reinforcement given only occasionally.
Laboratory research
in operant conditioning seems to show that once a behavior is established, it
is in fact better not to reward it after each occurrence; otherwise,
if for some
reason the constant reward suddenly ceases, the newlylearned behavior will also
cease, whereas behavior which is only intermittently reinforced is
very "resistent
to extinction"; it will even persist long after all rewards have
been totally
withdrawn.
6. As a final point, a distinction needs to be made between "primary"
and "secondary" reinforcers. Primary reinforcers are said
by behaviorists
to be those rewards to which an organism "naturally" responds (if it
is biologically normal): food during a state of hunger, water when
thirsty, sleep
when fatigued, sexual release during a state of sexual tension - these are all
primary reinforcers to which we are largely "pre-wired" to
respond and
for which we do not normally have to acquire a taste. Secondary reinforcers
This is the third of a three-part series on behaviorism from a
Christian perspective.MARY
STEWART VAN LEEUWEN
(and we will have reason to question these definitions a little later) are said
to be those acquired through association with primary reinforcers.
Thus, to return
to a practical illustration, the autistic child may begin by learning to make
sounds only for a food reward. But if that food reward (a primary reinforcer)
is always accompanied by the presence of his mother and her delighted
praise over
his accomplishment, then "mother's presence" and
"mother's praise"
become secondary reinforcers for which the child will eventually work
regardless
of whether they are accompanied by the more primary ones.
Since would-be behavior modifiers rarely want to follow around their
clients popping
food rewards into their mouths indefinitely, they tend to try to
"wean"
them from primary to more secondary reinforcers as quickly as
possible. This means
that even while primary reinforcers are the standard rewards, they
are accompanied
clearly and consistently by other things which can later act as
secondary or alternative reinforcers. In point of fact, just about anything can become a
secondary reinforcer.
The pokerchip "tokens" given to the mental patients in the casestudy
cited above are a clear example: like ordinary money, they have no
intrinsic value
to the one who possesses them; rather, they acquire their value by
their association
with other, more primary, reinforcers such as food, clothing, cigarettes, and
so forth. But even the setting in which primary reinforcement is
given may become
a secondary reinforcer. Thus the autistic child who has become used to getting
his food rewards (primary reinforcers) in his highchair may soon
perform desired
behaviors simply for the privilege of getting into the highchair
(which has become
a secondary reinforcer by its association with food). The process of
discovering
and exploiting secondary reinforcers is another skill exercised by
the professional
behavior modifier, but one which, once understood, is easily applied by the lay
worker as well.
Applied Behaviorism: What Can Christians Accept?
As we have stated in earlier parts of this essay, ontological, methodological,
and applied behaviorism all have a host of critics,' whose guiding values, if
not Christian, may be humanistic, rationalistic, Marxist or whatever. And so it
is not simply applied behaviorism itself but also its critics which
must be judged
by the standards of biblical revelation. In the absence of thoughtful
reflection
guided by biblical principles, it is all too easy for Christians
either to accept
or reject unconditionally the entire enterprise of applied behaviorism. This is
hardly surprising, since it is our contention that applied
behaviorism is compatible
with certain biblical truths and incompatible with others. The difficulty comes
in distinguishing among these. What follows is a preliminary (and far
from exhaustive)
attempt to do so by discussing three common criticisms of applied
behaviorism.
Criticism 1: "Behavior modification techniques work on the assumption that
man is purely selfish, hedonistic pleasure-seeker motivated to work
only for the
sake of reward. "
This is a criticism which, from a Christian standpoint, is valid if the concept
of "reward" is too narrowly-defined, but invalid if it assumes that
man is intrinsically more self
132
sacrificial than we know him to be on the basis of biblical
revelation. To elaborate,
there is nothing in Scripture which contradicts the notion that even
the redeemed
man is a seeker after rewards: C. S. Lewis (who was otherwise no friend-indeed,
he was a deadly foe-of behaviorism)' points out in his essay, "The Weight
of Glory" that
The New Testament has lots to say about self-denial, but not about self-denial
as an end in itself. We are told to deny ourselves and to take up our crosses
in order that we may follow Christ (but) nearly every description of
what we shall
ultimately find if we do so contains an appeal to desire. If there
lurks in most
modern minds the notion that to desire our own good and earnestly to hope for
the enjoyment of it, is a bad thing, I submit that this notion has
crept in from
Kant and the Stoics and is no part of the Christian faith. Indeed, if
we consider
the unblushing promises of reward and the staggering nature of the
rewards promised
in the Gospels, it would seem that Our Lord finds our desires, not too strong,
but too weak. We are half-hearted creatures, footing about with drink and sex
and ambition when infinite joy is offered us, like an ignorant child who wants
to go on making mud pies in a slum because he cannot imagine what is meant by
the offer of a holiday at the sea. We are far too easily pleased.'
Lewis is making two very important points here: firstly (on the side
of the behaviorists),
an appeal to "reward" for work done (even the
"work" of learning
a new behavior) is not an intrinsically un-Christian notion. Indeed,
the opposite
assumption-that man at his highest can work in a purely
disinterested, self-sacrificial
manner-although it sounds superficially Christian, is actually a
legacy of optimistic
humanism and not of Christianity at all. Not only does God build the incentive
of ultimate heavenly rewards into the description of the redeemed
life (as Revelation
21 and 22 unashamedly show) but the entire history of His dealings with Israel
indicates clearly that God's people were regularly exposed to His
reward and favor
when they lived by his standards and to his chastisement when they did not. And
if the Creator in His wisdom assumes the need for immediate and
long-range incentives
in us, we are scarcely being un-Christian in assuming like needs in
one another.
Having thus apparently opened the door to the unapologetic use of
behavior modification
techniques by Christian parents and teachers, let me hasten to make a
second very
important qualifying point from Lewis' quote. Lewis points out that "Our
Lord finds our desires not too strong, but too weak;" this leads us to the
very important consideration of what constitutes a "reward"
or reinforcer
in a behavior modification scheme. A little earlier, we spoke of the
behaviorist
distinction between "primary" and "secondary"
reinforcement.
This distinction, in its extreme form, assumes that man's only
"built-in"
motivation is that of physical comfort, and that all other motives (desire for
approval, desire for satisfying work, desire to learn, desire to find
the meaning
of life) are simply derived from the primary incentive to work for
physical comfort.
Such an assumption would hold, for instance, that a child's interst
in religious
matters derives from the fact that his parents reinforce him with "social
approval" for such interest, and that child's capacity to be reinforced by
the parents' social approval in turn derives from the fact that the parents are
the ones who feed, clothe, and protect him. Now it cannot be
emphasized too strongly
that this "hedonistic assumption," about the nature of man is no less
a faith-assumption of ontological behaviorism than the
JOURNAL OF THE AMERICAN SCIENTIFIC AFFILIATION
APPLIED BEHAVIORISM
assumptions of determinism, materialism, and "mental processlessness"
with which we dealt earlier. It is an assumption (or hypothesis) which precedes
behaviorist research-not one which has been unequivocally demonstrated by it,
as some seem to believe. While not all applied behaviorists adhere to
this ''hedonistic
assumption," it is part and parcel of ontological behaviorism and as such
constantly creeps into behavior modification schemes when they are applied by
unreflective people or by those who are tempted to see the entire behaviorist
enterprise as some kind of gospel for the solution to all man's problems.
The practical question is not whether Christians should exercise the authority
which accompanies whatever office we fill, but the style in which
that authority
is exercised by the Christian.
What is wrong with such an assumption from a Christian standpoint? After all,
isn't it true that without the basic physical necessities such as
food, shelter,
and sleep nothing else would get done? True, but "is not life
more than food,
and the body more than clothing?' 16 If we are made in God's image,
then included
among our most basic motives will be such things as the desire to do creative,
meaningful work,' the desire for fellowship,' the desire for "play,"'
and (if we are true to our biblical image of man) none of these can be assumed
to be mere derivatives from the desire for food, shelter, sleep or sex. Indeed,
biblically speaking, the most basic need of all men (if they could
only recognize
it) is not their need for physical survival, but their need for reconciliation
with their Maker. "Thow hast made us for Thyself, and our hearts
are restless
until they find their rest in Thee," wrote Saint Augustine. God Himself is
man's "primary reinforcer," and we forget this scandalous truth only
at our own peril-"for what shall it profit a man if he gain the
whole world,
and lose his soul?""
So what does all this mean for the judicious use of behavior
modification by Christians?
In practical terms, it means that the physical rewards of food,
candy, cigarettes
and trinkets so over-employed by so many behavior modifiers should not be used
unless it has become abundantly clear that the person is temporarily incapable
of responding to the "higher order" reinforcers such as
social fellowship,
the opportunity for creative work or play, the opportunity to exercise aristic
talents-yes, even the opportunity to worship and learn more about
God. For despite
man's profound and inbuilt ambivalence towards that "ultimate reward"
of reconciliation with God, we should expect to find traces of that
yearning for
God even in emotionally disturbed, autistic, or retarded
children-especially when
they have been claimed by their parents for God's kingdom through
baptism or dedication.''
Even the recent research literature on behavior modification is
beginning to caution
against the naive over-use of
SEPTEMBER 1979
tangible, physical rewards in situations where they are not needed.
In one study,
it was shown that children who originally showed a spontaneous
interest in coloring
activities tended to stop doing so after they had been systematically rewarded
with a gold ribbon for being "good colorers." They had, it
was concluded,
been transformed from happy amateurs who colored for the sake of coloring into
mercenary professionals who now required tangible rewards for the exercise of
their talents. The research report concludes with a warning against the use of
"extrinsic rewards'' in situations where it is clear that
''intrinsic rewards"
(such as satisfaction in the mere doing of the activity) are already
at work."
Christians can welcome this developing recognition among behavior
modifiers that
their original notions about ''rewards" were far too simplistic-but they
should be warned that there often still exists a tendency to resort
to primitive
physical rewards as the "easy way out." We know of this temptation in
our own lives as parents: it's easier to give the child a cookie when
he scrapes
his knee than to take the time to comfort him or read him a story.
And the cookie
"works"-at least in the short run. So do cigarettes and candies when
used as reinforcers for learning new behaviors-but do we really want
the wholesale
addictions to sugar and nicotine which can be the long-term results?
It is ironic
that the behavior modification community includes both those who routinely use
cigarettes and candy as reinforcers for new behaviors and those who, for a fee,
will help you to eliminate your nicotine and calorie dependencies through the
use of behavior modification techniques! Beware, therefore, lest an
over-reliance
on primitive, lower-order reinforcers turn you into someone who is educating a
child or adult for dependence rather that for responsible freedom-into someone
who more resembles a drug-pusher than a true teacher.
Criticism 2: "The practice of Behavior modification divides
people into two
classes: the 'controllers,' who know and practice the system and the
'controlled'
who must submit in passive, ignorant helplessness. This then opens the door to
authoritarian, totalitarian regimes."
Like the first criticism we considered, this second one is both valid
and invalid,
Christianly speaking, depending on certain other considerations. It is invalid
if it assumes that there is something intrinsically wrong with the
existence and
exercise of authority and the capacity for control which accompanies
that authority.
But it is valid inasmuch as it reflects a concern about the potential
for exercising
control in a powerhungry fashion with no acknowledgement of accountability for
the way it is used. Again, let us elaborate both qualifactions of
this criticism.
Catholic theologian Michael Novak, in a recent essay on
behaviorism" comments
that "there is a widespread belief, in this Protestant (sic) nation, that
Christianity is a religion of individualism, each man his own priest and pope,
each conscience inviolable, each person a potential source of
autonomy and dissent."
Novak then goes on to point out that this concept of man as a free, autonomous
being answerable only to himself and perfectly justified in resisting any and
all attempts at control is a legacy of the Enlightenment, and not of
Christianity
at all (however much the church has been mistakenly tainted by this
teaching.)
133MARY STE WART VAN LEEUWEN
Three critical factors tell against the model of Christianity as individualism:
the teachings of the scriptures; the practice of early Christianity,
and the actualities
of Christian life. The reaction against an exaggerated and errant (although in
some ways helpful) emphasis on individualism has been well under way
for several
decades .... Professor Skinner's emphasis on the social character of
human existence
is thus, from a theological point of view, confirmatory of a well-established
trend)'
Hence legitimate authority in the context of community is not to be
confused with
authoritarianism, and Christians are to listen to the voice of Scripture, not
to the drumbeat of secular humanism, in deciding what circumscribes
the exercise
of control in applied behaviorism. The biblical view of man and society clearly
includes authority structuresparents over children, husbands over
wives, the state
over its citizens, the judge over the criminal, the church elders
over the congregation-and
for this reason Christians need not reject applied behaviorism on the alltoo-popular
grounds that it smacks of "control" and that "control of anyone
by anyone else is always intrinsically bad." It isn't. Indeed, according
to Scripture, the fruit of rebellion against legitimate authority is not sweet
tolerance and freedom but chaotic and ugly self-seeking (as the book of Judges
vividly testifies in documenting an era when "each man did what was right
in his own eyes" 5). Only a naively optimistic view about the
perfectibility
of man holds otherwise.
Again, lest I appear to be opening the door to the very excercise of despotism
so feared by the secular critics of applied behaviorism, let me
qualify the above
remarks. The critics of behaviorism do well to be concerned about the misuse of
behavioral technology in the hands of the unscrupulous-or even simply
in the hands
of those who trust too naively in the claims of the system. Observing
the trends
in British government, law, and social science in the post-war
period, C.S. Lewis
took up his pen at almost the same time Skinner was writing Walden II and
produced
an anti-behaviorist fantasy novel called That Hideous Strength." In this
novel too, science has been given a blank check (this time by the government of
a country rather than an experimental community) to perfect man and
further harness
the powers of nature. Here too, an elite of specialists works for the supposed
greater good of mankind. The difference between Walden II and Belbury
(the scientific
think-tank of Lewis' novel) is that the planners in the latter
situation, through
willful misuse of their power, through sheer ignorance of their own
limitations,
or a combination of both, degenerate into a dog-eat-dog competition
for control.
This competition eventually ends in the destruction of the entire institution
and the merciful restoration of normal life to the surrounding area,
whose people
and resources had been appropriated and manipulated in the name of
progress. Lewis'
novel is, of course, no less a work of fiction than Skinner's, and his negative
version of the results of a scientifically-planned society no less speculative
than Skinner's positive one. To support his case for the finiteness
and depravity
of man, he appeals to the evidence of history and of Scripture, while Skinner
appeals to the past achievements of science and the present successes
of behavior
modification as evidence that man can not only plan his own destiny, but do so
without necessarily abusing the accompanying power. Adherence to
either position
takes the reader beyond evidence to basic faith-assumptions about
man's capacity
for unlimited progress and goodness.
134
How, then, are Christians to walk the fine line between legitimate exercise of
authority and sinful degeneration into despotic authoritarianism? We
are not guaranteed
immunity from the temptation to assume selfish power in a way that is being so
consistently role-modelled for us in the twentieth century
industrialized world.
However, a few reminders from the scriptural comments about authority may be of
help.
Whatever authority a Christian exercises in the offices of parent,
teacher, husband,
employer, or governor is never self-generated, but is derived from God Himself,
accountable to Him, and therfore to be exercised with an awe verging
on fear and
trembling. Our office is not accorded to us because of any intrinsic merit: we
are as fallen and prone to sin as those under our command. And so the apostle
Paul, even as he admonishes children to obey their parents and servants their
masters, promptly warns those same parents and masters not to abuse
their authority
"knowing that both their Master and yours is in heaven, and
there is no partiality
with Him."" The practical question is not whether Christians should
exercise the authority which accompanies whatever office we fill-be it parent,
teacher or whatever. Let me rather suggest four important questions regarding
the style in which that authority-and its accompanying power to
dispense rewards
and punishments-is exercised by the Christian.
Firstly, in what spirit are you exercising control? Are you trying to
change the
person's behavior in order to indulge your own desire for power? Are
you exercising
control to compensate for the frustration of being controlled by other people
or other circumstances, pecking order fashion? Are you putting on a
show of authority
to cover up your own uncertainties about the situation? Are you merely trying
to tailor the other person's behavior to fit your peculiar needs and
idiosyncrasies?
None of these, I submit, are valid motives for resorting to the powerful tools
of behavior modification. Ontological behaviorism may insist that the existence
of such motives (being irrelevant internal mental processes) makes no
difference
whatsoever to the effectiveness of a behavior modification
program-but such thinking
must be resolutely rejected. Just as God discerns and judges the spirit behind
an action, so do those over whom we exercise authority-and that
spirit makes all
the difference in the world as to the effectiveness of our program. In the long
run, only when fueled by a sincere and unselfish desire for the
other's good will
any attempt at behavioral control succeed. Again, this is a truth that is being
brought home to applied behaviorists by the realities of their
accumulating professional
experience. The architect of one behavior modification project with difficult
children in a California school system has concluded that
sincerity is an integral part of instruction in behaviorial engineering
The teachers working with (me) on the experiment have sometimes
doubted each other's
sincerity. One person compliments another, who says 'You're just
reinforcing me!'
And the response is 'Oh, the hell I am! I really mean it!' With the
kids and the
staff, we've had to continually stress being sincere. You should
really want the
other person to change."
Secondly, for what are you exercising control? Is your
long-term goal the training of an equal, fellow-member of the Body of
Christ-someone
who may well at some future
JOURNAL OF THE AMERICAN SCIENTIFIC AFFILIATION
APPLIED BEHAVIORISM
time be in a position of responsible authority over you,
circumstances and gifts
permitting? Or are you, consciously or unconsciously, playing the role of the
animal-trainer, educating for a more and more total dependence on yourself? If
the latter, then beware! You are not God; any sovereignty you have
over the life
of another exists only to direct that other to the true Master of us
all. We are
called to be willing bondsiaves of Jesus Christ and Him alone: deference to all
other legitimate authority is the by-product of obedience to Him, and
cannot-indeed,
dare notexist on its own.
Thirdly, how independently are you exercising behavioral control? As
Christians,
we are given the gifts of prayer, Scripture, and the counsel of
fellow-believers
as safeguards against our sinful tendency to distort reality. Is the
use of behavioral
techniques being subjected to these three courts of appeal for
endorsement, modification,
or outright rejection? In particular I would stress the
responsibility of believing
bodies of Christians not to be intimidated by the scientistic
trappings of behaviorism:
it is for us to hold applied behaviorism accountable to the standards
of the Word,
and not vice-versa.
Finally, how hastily are you resorting to the techniques of behavioral control?
A recent reviewer of the behavior modification scene reported suprise when one
of the most prestigious pioneers of behavior modification introduced
a token-reinforcement
system into a highly disruptive seventh-grade class "only as a last resort
after more traditional methods had failed to end the chaos, When I asked why,
he replied, 'Why use tokens when something else will work?' "a
If a non-Christian
specialist in applied behaviorism employs his tools only as a last resort, we
would do well to ask ourselves why. I suspect that the emerging cautiousness of
such practitioners reflects their growing awareness that learning is not simply
a matter of tangible rewards and punishments, however much of these
do enter into
the picture. Indeed, a constant reliance on such rewards and
punishments may simply
cause the child to regress to notions of primitive reciprocity
("you scratch
my back and I'll scratch yours") in his dealing with others when, in fact,
his behavior was already quite amenable to change based on an appeal to reason,
emotion, religious conviction or a combination of all three.
Ontological behaviorism
does not make room for the possibility that children may pass through definite
stages in their social, intellectual, and moral development (with a rewards-andpunishments
orientation a legitimate, but very immature phase in that development)."
Rather it assumes that the stimulus-response laws of respondent and
operant conditioning
are the sole vehicle of learning for all organisms (animal or human, normal or
abnormal) at all ages and stages of life. But the truth of the matter is that
we know far too little about the degree to which these techniques
pioneered almost
exclusively on animals and "marginal" human beings-such as retardates
and severly disturbed personsare applicable without substantial qualification
to persons leading ordinary lives in ordinary homes, classrooms and workplaces.
The track record of applied behaviorism increasingly suggests that a
healthy skepticism
is warranted.
Criticism 3: "By locating all causes for behavior change in the
environment,
behavior modification programs deny, or at least ignore, the existence of free
will, and hence assign human beings no credit for their accomplishments and no
blame for their misdeeds."
SEPTEMBER 1979
This final criticism to which this paper addresses itself is a rather complex
argument to handle from a Christian point of view, given the
theological differences
which have historically existed within the church regarding the part played by
man's will in the process of both Salvation and Sanctification. But I
am personally
inclined to agree with Novak,2' when he maintains that the thrust of Scripture
is such as to give man no credit for anything good he does (all such goodness
being rooted in the grace of God), but, on the other hand, to hold him (but for
the work of Christ) fully responsible for his sinful deeds even while
acknowledging
that such sin is not merely personal because the entire creation has
been flawed
by man's fall and is never totally supportive of good actions. This is one of
the apparent paradoxes of Scripture which is hardly amenable to analysis by the
fragile tools of human logic-but even so, it does shed light on two
issues regarding
the Christian's attitude to applied behaviorism: firstly, if the source of our
goodness lies outside ourselves, then we need not reject applied
behaviorism merely
on the grounds that it denies man due "credit" for his good
deeds. True,
behaviorism errs in citing not God, but the environment as the ultimate source
of man's accomplishments; but the opposite position whereby man
himself is exalted
as the autonomous source of all noble actions is simply another legacy of the
humanistic rejection of God and His replacement by so-called autonomous man as
the center of the universe. Hence we can agree with Novak when he
supports Skinner
to the extent of saying "at no point is man's autonomy such that
he can take
credit for it. Such as it is, it has been given to him, both in its
abiding tendencies
and in its actual exercise. It is 'grace' or 'gift,' rather than his
own creation,"
although as a Christian he then parts ways with Skinner in affirming that the
ultimate source of that gift is in God and not (or only secondarily)
in the impersonal
pressures of the environment. "Hence," (he concludes) 'theonomy"
rather that 'autonomy' is a more accurate name for the human
reality.""
On the other hand (and this is my second point) if the source of our
badness lies
essentially within ourselves, and we are answerable for it, then the Christian
and behaviorist views of justice must diverge quite radically from one another.
For it will be recalled that, according to strict ontological
behaviorism, man's
behavior (aside from certain genetically-programmed dispositions) is
totally determined
by the events of his environment and that for this reason both personal freedom
and the personal credit (i.e., "dignity") resulting from
our accomplishments
are illustory. By the same reasoning, however, the notions of
personal responsibility
and accountability are also illustory: if my enviroment is to be credited with
my achievements, it must also take the blame for my mistakes and misdeeds. This
leads to a philosophy of justice according to which law-breakers are regarded
not as responsible agents who have willingly and knowingly violated
certain standards
of conduct, but as persons whose misdeeds should either be entirely overlooked
("Poor fellow-he's just a victim of his past!") or at most treated as
"illnesses" needing to be "cured," rather than as
"sins"
needing to be "punished." At first glance, this seems like
a very enlightened
attitude; but in point of fact, its practical application results all too often
in one of two opposite abuses: either the victimization of society at large or
(paradoxical as it may seem) of the criminal himself.MARY STEWART VAN
LEEUWEN
If the Source of our badness lies essentially within ourselves, and
we are answerable
for it, then the Christian and behaviorist views of justice must diverge quite
radically from one another.
With regard to the first abuse, the growing tendency to regard the criminal as
"more sinned against (by his environment) than sinning" appears to be
generating a state of increasing judicial anarchy in the western world. Reduced
or suspended sentences have become increasingly the norm even for what used to
be regarded as serious crimes-with no accompanying evidence that this attitude
of sympathy and leniency has in any way reduced the likelihood that
the criminal
will repeat his offence." In the traditional system of criminal law,
vengeance and retribution were recognized as important threads of the
social fabric,
not because they deterred or reformed the offender, but because they reasurred
and satisfied the offended. This was not the satisfaction of some dark animal
need. Citizens entered into the social contract with the
understanding that society
would guarantee-or at least put a premium on-their lives, dignity,
and the right
to enjoy their possessions. It was only when retribution followed injury that
citizens could be reassured and satisfied that society really did
place some value
on other persons. This wasand is-a central need for any society. And, just as
excessive or unjust punishment brutalizes the offender because it suggests that
he is of no value, insufficient punishment brutalizes the victim for the same
reason. 14
These are not words written by a Christian journalist-but we can echo
her sentiments
when we recall that Romans 13 speaks of the civil government (whether
she realizes
this fact or not) as being "God's servant for your good. .
.(and) the servant
of God to execute his (i.e., God's) wrath on the wrongdoer."
But one result of the ascendency of a behaviorist view of crime has
been the unquestioned
assumption that it is only environments, not people, that can be held
accountable
for crime. Consequently, the state whose penal system rests on such
an assumption
may violate the biblical imperative in two serious ways: In the first place, it
assumes that persons are not born prone to evil, but are merely tabulae rasae
("blank slates") on which the environment alone writes the program of
our subsequent behavioral tendencies. By this reckoning, crime is totally the
outcome of poverty or deprived social conditions-although this, (continues the
same journalist)
does not explain why the overwhelming majority of poor Canadians do not commit
crimes, nor why so many well-off ones do, (nor why), during the 1950's- 1970's
when Canadians were enjoying rapidly im
proving standards of living and social services unequalled in any other period
of history, the crime rates-instead of going downwere rapidly going
up,"
In the second place, in refusing to exercise its retributive mandate
against the
wrongdoer, the behaviorist-leaning penal system, and the state which condones
it, have failed to strike the balance between justice and mercy
demanded by biblical
norms for society.
136
Regardless of whether punishment deters or rehabilitates, it is necessary for
justice .... Cynicism and callous indifference to good and evil are
the products
of a society that, like ours, is less concerned with the needs of
those who observe
its rules than with those who break them."
If journalists of the secular press-without the privilege of biblical faith or
literacy-are, on the basis of the observed chaos in criminal justice, appealing
for a return to a more biblical view of crime and punishment, it
should give thinking
Christians much cause for reflection on the type of government they
wish to support
in the future.
But the victimization of society by criminals held inadequately responsible for
their actions is only one result of adherence to an environmental determinist
view of behavior. The other, strange as it may seem, concerns the
likelihood that
the criminal himself will be unjustly victimized. For it is not always the case
that behavioristinfluenced penal systems end up doing nothing to the criminal,
on the grounds that his crime is "really his environment's
fault, not his."
It is just as likely that such a theory of criminal treatment may
very well acknowledge
that the offender's environment has indeed disposed him towards
continuous wrong-doing
and that he therefore merits the privilege of re-education at the
state's expense.
C. S. Lewis was prophetically sensitive to the hidden potential for injustice
inherent in such a view when the jargon of criminal
"rehabilitation'' first
began to replace the traditional notion of "retribution" in the minds
of penologists a quarter of a century ago. According to this newly-fashionable
theory (Lewis called it ''The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment"), when a
criminal himself is held responsible for his crime and punished accordingly, he
is being victimized by a barbarous and unenlighteded spirit of revenge, whereas
when he is exposed rather to "treatment," "rehabilitation,"
or "reeducation," he is being treated in an enlightened and
scientific
manner which is kinder to the criminal and also promotes the goals of
future crime-deterrence.
"Thus," (in changing from retributive to a behaviorist
theory of penology)
"it appears at first sight that we have passed from the harsh
and self-righteous
notion of giving the wicked their deserts to the charitable and enlightened one
of tending the psychologically sick."" But, Lewis goes on to say, let
us not be fooled by a change in terminology:
the things done to the criminal, even if they are called cures, will be
just as compulsory as they were in the old days when we called them
punishments. If a tendency to steal can be cured by psychotherapy,
the thief will
no doubt be forced to undergo the treatment."
Even worse, Lewis warned, once a person passes from the category of
"morally
wrong" to the category of "psychologically sick, " then there is
an accompanying loss of precision both in the definition of what is
"sick"
and the definition of what constitutes adequate
"treatment." Seriously
"sick " people, having no specialized knowledge themselves
of medicine,
must necessarlily trust their doctors to know both that they really are sick,
and what and how long it will take to treat them. The traditional
concept of "deserved"
punishment was rooted in the notion that not just a specialized elite, but that
all adults capable of functioning in society were able to distinguish between
lawful and unlawful acts. Once we concede that people passively
"catch"
bad behavior from their environment in the same way they
"catch" measles
or
JOURNAL OF THE AMERICAN SCIENTIFIC AFFILIATIONAPPLIED BEHAVIORISM
bubonic plague, then it is up to the specialists both to diagnose the disease
and prescribe the cure. In extreme cases, the sick person can be
quarantined indefinitely
for his own good and the good of society, whether he likes it or not. Hence an
additional danger of a behaviorist-rooted theory of penology is that
the definite
sentence for a definite type of crime, to which traditional
jurisprudence adhered,
may be replaced by an indefinite sentence which can be lengthened or shortened
at the discretion of the psychological "experts."
A further danger is that, having conceded to specialists their superior wisdom
in defining what is "criminally sick," we may find ourselves, under
an unscrupulous political regime, being labelled "sick" and forced to
undergo "treatment" for any opinion or practice that is
deemed threatening
to the status quo.
We know that one school of psychology already regards religion as a neurosis.
When this particular neurosis becomes inconvenient so government,
what is to hinder
government from proceeding to 'cure' it? . . And thus when the
command is given,
every prominent Christian in the land may vanish overnight into
Institutions for
the treatment of the ideologically unsound, and it will rest with the
expert gaolers
to say when (if ever) they are to re-emerge. But it will not be
persecution. Even
if the treatment is painful, even if it is life long, even if it is fatal, that
will only be a regrettable accident; the intention was purely therapeutic. In
ordinary medicine, there were painful operations and fatal
operations; so in this.
But because they are 'treatment,' not punishment, they can be criticized only
by fellow experts and on technical grounds, never by men as men and on grounds
of justice."
Eager to assimilate and apply these "progressive" concepts of prison
reform, the Britain of the early 50's would give Lewis no hearing for
his arguments
(he finally published them in an Australian legal journal.) It was
only a little
later, however, that the first reports of so called brainwashing
procedures began
to leak out of China. A recent Skinnerian critic writes:
When China began industrialization, it adopted procedures much
like those described in Beyond Freedom and Dignsty. It often applied
reinforcement
rather than aversive methods to induce its people to accept the new behavioral
environment. It then arranged its reward system so as to positively reinforce
actions that were in conformity with the values of the new
environment. Deviation
was not so much punished as it was treated. Recalcitrant individuals were given
group-think treatments-called brain-washing-in which they were
rewarded for expressing
approved sentiments. °
The judicious arrangement of reinforcers in the outside
environment has now been buttressed by the use of drugs to alter-or
at least render
innocuousthe internal minds of dissidents in Russia, as Solzhenitsyn and others
have reported. And lest we be tempted to think that such abuses
(naive or deliberate)
could "never happen here," it needs to be pointed out that
in California
(unquestionably the most eager state in the union when it comes to
employing the
latest ideas from psychology and the personnel to implement them),
since the introduction
of rehabilitative, behavior modification types of prison programs in
the fifties,
"the median term served by 'felony first releases' has risen from twenty
to thirty-six months-twice the national average."" This
strongly suggests
the materialization of Lewis' fears of "indefinite
sentencing." Reports
from prisons in other parts of the country where behavior modification programs
are in use stress repeatedly that prisoners would "rather have remained in
solitary confinement"" than take part. A typical program consists
SEPTEMBER 1979
of several differenct "levels" of privileges that the prisoner must
attain by displaying the right behavior, which is rewarded by the distribution
of token-points by guards and psychiatric staff
on their own arbitrary discretion. . . Inmates are awarded tokens for
proper responses
to guards, such as 'Good morning sir? how are you, sir? Yes, sir,' etc . . . .
(During group therapy, the prisoner's therapist) will point out what problems
as inmate has, and, whether they're real or not, that inmate is
required to solve
his problem in the group. If the inmate doesn't try to solve this
problem forced
on him, then he's not cooperating with the behavior modification program, which
results in a hard way to go on all fronts. One way in which an inmate
is harassed
is in receiving less tokens per day. Since tokens are given out by
stateemployed
personnel at their own discretion, an inmate could find himself in a
tight situation
if he starts receiving just enough tokens for everyday necessities and nothing
else .... if one doesn't have enough tokens to pay rent, one is simply thrown
(down to a lower level) for a period of time."
In this program, too, the uncertainty of indefinite sentencing is routine:
It usually takes a six-month period for one who is cooperating with
the behavior
modification program to complete it and be transferred out. However, with this
arbitrary means of distributing tokens, and in the name of therapy, an inmate
can be forced to remain (in the program) until the maximum of his sentence is
up.
These anecdotal reports come to us from individual inmates who, it
can be argued,
are hardly supplying us with careful documentation and may, in
addition, be prone
to exaggeration. But confirmation of the agonies of
"indeterminate sentencing"
comes from another, more articulate source-one who might be expected to support
the status quo of the prison system, not oppose it: Charles Colson was a crack
Washington lawyer and Richard Nixon's top aide who, in the wake of
his conversion
to Christianity decided to plead guilty to certain Watergateconnected offenses
and take no privileges for the duration of his prison sentence. Now
working full
time in the cause of prison reform, he writes in his
recently-published autobiography,
that one of the most agonizing aspects of prison life is the guessing
game which
all inmates must constantly play with regard to the probability of
being paroled
or not at their next hearing-a probability which appears to be almost totally
determined by the caprice of an overworked, underinformed committee. "
One is also reminded of the question, raised in an earlier part of this essay,
as to whether or not environmental manipulation of behavior can work
at all effectively
if the target of that manipulation is a human being who knows, or has guessed,
the nature of those manipulations and simply decided that he does not
agree with
their goals. Again, the first-hand reports of prisoners in behavior
modification
programs would suggest not: "The guards put on a front of
politeness, concern,
and friendship. I had had enough of the cells, guards, and phoniness those few
hours between the 6th and 7th of April and refused to eat or talk to
anyone."
Fellow inmates co-operating with the program are regarded no less
cynically: they
are
brain-washed inmates . . . stool pigeons, snitches, puppets, and
serve the purpose
of carrying out the personnel's wishes to a fuller degree. These
inmates set 'examples'
for the newer block residents, advocate block policy, and of course
keep the personnel
up on all the activities of inmates whom officials are keeping a close eye on,
and especially those inmates who are in opposition to the program."
In light of such comments, Lewis' words of two and one
137
MARY STEWART VAN LEEUWEN
half decades ago ring particularly prophetic:
To undergo all those assaults on my personality which modern psycho
therapy knows
how to deliver; to he taken without consent from my home and friends; to lose
my liberty; to be remade after some pattern of normality' hatched in a Viennese
(or Harvardian?)'5 laboratory to which I never professed allegiance;
to know that
this process will never end until either my captors have succeeded or
I grow wise
enough to cheat them with apparent success-who cares whether this is
called Punishment
or not? That it includes most of the elements for which any
punishment is feared-shame,
exile, bondage, and years eaten by the locust-is obvious. Only
enormous ill-desert
could justify it; but ill-desert is the very conception which
the Humanitarian theory has thrown overboard''
This lengthy discussion of the potential for abuse inherent in applied behaviorism-abuse
of the rights of the law-abiding majority, but also of the
crime-performing minority-is
intended to emphasize the fact that Christian responsibility for the
uses of these
techniques extends beyond the confines of our individual lives as the parents
and teachers of children and into the very bedrock of our society and
the social
consequences of its policies. We are living with the legacy of
several centuries
of combined belief in the "science ideal" (the notion that the entire
universe is impersonal and mechanistic) and the "freedom ideal" (the
notion that man, on his own can somehow transcend his own determinism and play
God)-and both ontological and applied behaviorism are part and parcel of this
legacy. Change will not come easily-partly because of the
longstanding and pervasive
nature of this "alternative religion," but also partly because, for
all its errors, it is not totally lacking in elements of biblical truth, as I
have tried to indicate. This makes the business of separating wheat from chaff
one which requires all of the wisdom that the Holy Spirit can give to us, both
as individuals and as interdependent members of the one Body of Christ. It also
renders very challenging the business of deciding under what circumstances we
should or should not support the schemes of applied behaviorism, and (just as
important) the process of articulating clearly, forcefully-and if
necessary, sacrificially-our
reasons for taking either of these stands at a particular time. This
trio of articles
has been a preliminary attempt to provide some Christian guidelines
to that end.
REFERENCES
Some standard works which discuss ease studies and principles of
behavior modification
include
a) Allyon, T. and Azrin, N. The Token Economy: A Motivational
System for Therapy and Rehabilitation. New York: Appleton-CenturyCrofts, 1968.
b) Honig W.K. (Ed.) Operant Behavior: Areas of Research and Applica
tion. New York: Appteton-Century-Crofts, 1966,
e)Wolpe, J. The Practice of Behavior Therapy. New York; Pergamon, 1969.
'See particularly, Wheeler, H. (Ed.) Beyond the Punitive Society, San
Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company, 1973.
'A criticism repeatedly levelled by Noam Chomsky. See his essay
''Psychology and
Ideology" in his anthology For Reasons of State. New York: Random House,
1973.
'To the best of my knowledge, Lewis never tackled behaviorism by that name and
probably was not even in touch with the actual psychology literature on it. But
his aversion to a behaviorist world-view is clear in his novel That
Hideous Strength
(London: John Lane the Bodley Head Ltd., 1945), his essay "The
Humanitarian
Theory of Punishment" (1949; reprinted in God in the Dock, Grand Rapids:
Eerdmans, 1970), and his Abolition of Man, London: Wm. Collins & Sons Ltd.,
1943.
"The Weight of Glory," in a collection by the same title.
Grand Rapids, Eerdmans, 1965
5 Matt. 6:25
'cf. Genesis 1-2
'As implied in the triune nature of God and the "Body" analogy of the
church which Paul develops in 1 Cor. 12 and Eph. 4.
'Psalm 104:26 'Mark g:36
Dale Evans Rogers' Angel Unaware and Brother Andrew's God's
Smuggler both contain heartwarming accounts of the spontaneous
religious impulse
in retarded children.
"Greene, 0. and Lepper, MR. "How to Turn Play Into
Work." Psycho
logy Today, September, 1974, pp. 49-54.
''Novak, M. "Is He Really a Grand Inquisitor?" in Wheeler, Op. Cit.
pp. 230-246.
''ibid., p.232.
''Judges 17:6, 21:25
"Lewis, CS. That Hideous Strength. London: John Lane the Bodley Head Ltd.,
1945.
''Ephesians 6:19
"Gray, F., Granbard, P.S., and Rosenberg, H. "Little
Brother is Changing
You." Psychology Today, March 1974, pp. 42-46.
"Goodall, K. "Shapers at Work." Psychology Today,
November, 1972.
pp. 53-62, 132-13g.
"See particularly the writings of Jean Piaget and Lawrence Kohtberg for an
elaboration of this position.
"Novak, M. Op. Cit., p.233.
211bid., p. 234.
"Amiel, B. "The Chaos of Criminal Justice in Canada." Saturday
Night,
Sept. 1975, 19-25.
"Ibid.
"ibid.
"Ibid.
"Lewis, CS. "The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment," in God in
the
Dock Grand Rapids: Eerdmnns, 1970.
''Ibid.
"Ibid.
"Wheeler, H. "A Non-Punitive World?" in Wheeler, H.
(Ed.) Op. Cit.,
p. 19.
''Babbage, SB. "CS. Lewis and the humanitarian theory of punishment"
Christian Scholar's Review, 1972, 2(3) 234-235.
"Nicholson, W.G. "Michigan intensive program center," R. T.: A
Journal
of Radical Therapy, 1975, 4(6).
"ibid.
"Colson, C. Born Again. Old Toppan, N.J.: Chosen Books, 1975.
"Nicholson, Op. Cit.
"My parentheses.
"Lewis, CS. "The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment.
138