Science in Christian Perspective
Truth : Mathematical and Biblical
DAVID L. NEUHOUSER
Dapartment of Mathematics
Taylor University
Upland, Indiana 46989
From: JASA 31
(March 1979): 29-33.
Presented at the 1976 Annual Meeting of the ASA at Wheaton
College.
Is the statement, "You can't prove that God exists" true or false? Of
course, the meaning of the words is of crucial importance in
attempting to answer
that question. In particular, there are two eligible, and quite
different, meanings
for the word "prove." One definition for the word "prove"
would he the usual definition that mathematicians use. A second would
he a logical
argument which would convince every sane per
son. As we shall see, these two definitions are not the same at all.
Basic Assumptions
In every mathematical system certain statements are
assumed to be true. These assumptions are called axioms or postulates. To see
why it is necessary to have assumptions, (i.e., why it is impossible to prove
every statement) consider the following. To prove that statement, Si, is true
we must give a statement, S2, as a reason. Then to prove that S2 is
true we must
give another reason S3. This process must either continue
indefinitely, be circular,
or at some point come to a statement which we say is one of our basic
assumptions.
So in mathematics we prove statements (called theorems) by starting with axioms
and using logic or deductive reasoning. We are then certain that our theorems
are true if our assumptions are true. But if our assumptions are in doubt, then
we cannot be certain about our conclusions. We cannot use deductive reasoning
to prove that our axioms are true, because as we have seen, every mathematical
system must start with some assumptions. Therefore, in mathematics we can never
arrive at certainty. In fact, it's even worse: mathematicians are not
even interested
in whether or not a set of axioms is true. They ,would he happy if they could
just show that they are consistent. Even here they have trouble.
Kurt Godel, a mathematical logician, demonstrated in 1931 that if you
have a set
of axioms that's complete enough to give such a simple thing as the real number
system, then it cannot be proved to be consistent. Notice that he did
a very interesting
thing. Only mathematicians do these kinds of things. He proved that
it is impossible
to prove that a set of axioms is consistent.
Now, of course, we believe that they are consistent, but that is
exactly the point
I'm trying to make. We are reduced to the place where we must have
faith. We cannot
prove it. In fact, we even prove that we can't prove it.
Suppose we loosely define a religion as any discipline whose foundations rest on an element of faith , . there may or may not be reason present, but at least there has to be some element of faith. Quantum mechanics, for example, would be a religion tinder this definition. But mathematics would hold the unique position of being the only branch of theology possessing a rigorous demonstration of the fact that it should he so classified.1
So, in the first sense of the word "prove," we can prove
that God exists.
We just have to start with the right assumptions. But these assumptions may be
in doubt, in which ease the "proof" doesn't mean anything.
In the second
sense of the word we cannot prove that God exists, but we cannot prove (in this
second sense of the word) that God doesn't exist either.
Mathematical proof, then, consists of going from axioms to theorems by way of
deductive reasoning. Axioms are sometimes called postulates or assumptions, and
when this method is used in science they may be called hypotheses,
presuppositions,
and sometimes even laws. Today a set of assumptions used in science
is often called
a model. It is important to note that deductive reasoning cannot lead
its to these
axioms. Then what good is deductive reasoning? I believe there are at least two
very important things that reason does for us.
I. If through observation, experience, revelation, or any other method see come
to believe something, then reason can he used to deduce other things
(let's call
them conclusions). That is, if our hypothesis is true,
then our conclusions are true also and we have become (Aware of new truths or
at least truth in a new end per/saps more useful form.
11. The conclusions can be used to test the original hypothesis. If
the conclusions
(Agree with our experience, we have even snore faith in our hypothesis. But, if
the conclusions do not agree with our experience, our faith in the hypothesis
may be weak-cued or even destroyed.
Mathematical Method and Divine Revelation
Now, let us consider how the mathematical method (i.e., deductive reasoning),
the scientific method, and faith in divine revelation are related. As first it
would seem that revelation and the scientific method have nothing in
common. However,
when we consider the question, "Is a particular proposition or
set of propositions
a divine revelation?" it sounds a lot like the question,
"Is a particular
proposition or set of propositions a good scientific model or
theory?" Perhaps
there is some similarity in the way we might answer these questions.
Before attempting
an answer let us consider
the scientific method.
There may not even be such a thing as the scientific method. There
are certainly
different methods or procedures in different sciences. For example,
in some parts
of astronomy, geology, and biology the important method of repeated experiments
is not possible. Even so, I believe (note that at least an element of faith is
now a part of this paper even if evidence of learning never appears) there are
some things common to all scientific investigation. From my
background in mathematics,
I feel free to define the scientific method to be some of these
common elements.
In order to find these common elements, we start by looking at a popular, and
over-simplified, description of the scientific method. A scientist gathers and
organizes data. He then uses inductive reasoning to make generalizations. Since
I am a mathematician, I will call these generalizations postulates.
These postulates
are checked against all the data possessed by the scientist and new experiments
may he designed to test the generalizations further. These postulates
may he used
as premises and by means 0f deductive reasoning further
generalizations (or theories)
can be derived. These, of course, can be tested in the same way as postulates.
At each testing new data are obtained and the cycle of steps
repeated. It is the
scientist's belief that, in the long rut), this procedure gives
closer and closer
approximations to the truth about reality. Figure 1
illustrates this procedure.
{inexact representation of Fig 2.}
g data
asoning
ates
asoning
As an example of this, Isaac Newton observed various falling bodies (including apples and the moon). From these data he hypothesized that there is a force of attraction between every two objects which is directly proportional to the product of their masses and inversely porportional to the square of the distance between them. From this he could deduce Kepler's Law's of planetary motion and many other relations. Newton himself believed that this was the way the scientific method operated. In spite of Newton's belief, there seems to me to he one serious flaw in the whole scheme and that is the step where he went from the data to the formula by induction alone. It is certainly clear that Newton did go from the data to the formula, but 1 think that there must he more involved than inductive reasoning. Figure 2 is a modification of Figure 1 which shows some of these extra things. Please notice particularly the last of the added elements.
{inexact representation of fig 2., ed.}
^
|
|
|
testing
^
| |
|
testing
Before commenting further on these additions to the scientific
method, it should
be pointed out that the scientist does not begin at the top of these diagrams
with a completely open or unbiased mind. He has various
presuppositions, attitudes,
arid inclinations determined by his culture, psychological make-up, and overall
vision of the world. It is also possible, and even probable, that his
participation
in the scientific endeavor will modify these.
Physicist Werner Heisenberg said, "In fact, imagination plays a decisive
role in natural science. For even though we can hope to get at the facts only
after many sober and careful experiments, we can fit the facts
themselves together
only if we can feel rather than think our way into the
phenomena."2 Einstein
would even say that Figure 2 is not just a modification of
Figure 1
but a totally
different process. In his view,
the best path to be followed might not be that of observation followed by induction of general laws, but the totally different process of postulating a theory and then discovering whether or not the facts fitted it. Thus a theory should start with more scientific and philosophical assumptions than the facts alone warranted.2
One of these assumptions was his belief in the harmony of the universe.
Therefore, perhaps a better way of looking at the scientific method would he to
call the set of postulates a theory or model. This model is obtained
in some way
from data by means of induction, imagination, inspiration, etc. It seems to me
not unlikely that at times
Revelation is a gift to us from God, but our evaluation of it and acceptance of it may be a result of a reasoning process very much like the scientific method.
God gives some revelation of a scientific nature to a scientist,
whether the scientist
is a Christian or not. He works in mysterious ways his wonders to perform. In
whatever way this model is obtained it is essential that reason he
used to determine
whether or not it is acceptable. It must he checked against all kinds
of evidence.
It will probably seem to he in conflict with some of the evidence. This usually
is a surprise to most nonscientists. The scientist does not discard a
model just
because it contains some paradoxes. He compares it with other models. None will
be able to explain everything. All will probably involve paradoxes. None can be
proved by a single line of reasoning, so cumulative evidence is
important in determining
in which of the various models the scientist places his faith. From this time
on, the behavior of the scientist will depend, at least in part, on which model
he believes in and the degree of that belief.
How then does this relate to divine revelation? Suppose you receive
what you think
is a divine revelation. How do you know, in fact, that it is a revelation and
not just the result of an idea planted in your subconscious mind from
the combination
of a television show you saw last week and a dream you had last night, perhaps
aided by a touch of indigestion or the sight of a beautiful sunset? I think we
would have to use the same kind of testing we use for a scientific theory. John
Locke put it this way,
Whatever God bath revealed is certainly true: no doubt can be made of it. This is the proper object of faith: but whether it he a divine revelation or not, reason must judge , . . God when He makes the prophet does not unmake the man . . . I do out mean that we must eonstilt reason and examine whether a proposition revealed from God can be made out by natural principles and if it cannot then we may reject it: but consult it we must.4
Even Jeremiah was not always sure when he had received a revelation
until he checked
it against the evidence. Jeremiah 32:6 and 7 says, "and Jeremiah said, The
word of the Lord came unto me, saying, Behold, Hanameel the Son of
Shallum thine
uncle shall come unto thee, saying, Buy thee my field that is in Anathoth: for
the right of redemption is thine to buy it." Verse 8 tells how his uncle
came with the offer to buy the field and Jeremiah says, "Then I knew that
this was the word of the Lord."
In Matthew 11 we have another example of this type of testing of faith. Keep in
mind that the incidents reported in this chapter occurred after John
the Baptist's
declaration to the crowd on the occasion of the baptism of Jesus, "Behold
the Lamb of God, which taketh away the sin of the world." Now John sends
his disciples to inquire of Jesus, "Art thou he that should come or do we
look for another." Jesus does not costdemo John for his lack of faith, in
fact, he praises him as a prophet saying, "Among them that are
born of women
there bath not risen a greater than John the
Baptist." The answer Jesus gives is that they should look at the evidence.
"The blind receive their sight, and the lame walk, the lepers
are cleansed,
and the deaf hear, the dead are raised up, and the poor have the
gospel preached
to them."
The Greatest Model
Now let us consider the greatest revelation of all and the greatest
model of reality,
namely the biblical or Christian view of reality. We may not he able
to use reason
to arrive at this biblical view of reality, but we can use reason to check it.
Note also that we can say the very same thing about Einstein's Theory
of Relativity;
we may not be able to use reason to arrive at it but it can be checked by the
use of reason. Following is a list, although certainly not a complete list, of
some of the types of evidence for the biblical or Christian vie"
of reality.
1. The existence of moral low.
2. The truth of the biblical statements that con be verified.
3. Historical evidence of biblical events.
4. Personal experience and the personal experience of other Christians.
5. Scientific evidence.
6. The weaknes of alternative (i.e., non-Christian) models.
C. S. Lewis' book, Mere Christianity, discusses the
existence of moral law biblical statements that
as evidence, there are many can be checked by our experience or the results of natural or social science. None of These Diseases by Dr.
S. I. McMillan looks at many of God's commands to the Israelites in the light
of modern medical knowledge. History and Christianity by John W. Montgomery is
a good hook on historical evidence. The fourth point in the list may not sound
like part of the scientific method, but Heisenherg said, "science, too, is
based on personal experience, or on the experience of others reliably
reported."5
One example of scientific evidence is William Pollard's thesis, elaborated in
Chapter 4 of Physicist and Christian that every path of investigation of nature
leads to supernature. Many of C. S. Lewis' books (e.g., Miracles and
The Abolition
of Man) discuss various types of evidence. Perhaps none of these paths alone is
convincing to a given individual, but remember that the same thing was true in
the scientific method. The power of cumulative evidence is the really important
point here.
There are paradoxes in this model; for example, man's free will and
God's sovereignty, God's justice and mercy, and human suffering and God's love. We can't overlook
these problems, but paradoxes do not necessarily overthrow the model.6 There are
extremely difficult paradoxes in the mathematical system of real numbers, but
all the mathematicians I know have a great deal of faith in it.
Physicists cannot
reconcile the wave and particle nature of light, but they believe in
both. Whether
the paradoxes in the biblical theory of reality are enough to
overthrow a person's
faith depend upon the strength of the cumulative evidence and the weakness of
the alternative models. Atheism, for example, has the problem of
trying to answer
the questions of how personality can he produced by an impersonal universe or
how love and care can come from an unloving and uncaring universe. As
Elton Trueblnnd
has said,
"A believer believes in God partly because he is unable to make a leap of
faith as great as the atheist is forced to make."7
My conclusion is that the process of understanding and coming to have faith in
divine revelation is very much similar to the process of
understanding and coming
to have faith in a scientific model. I realize that revelation is a gift to us
from God, but our evaluation of it and acceptance of it may be a
result of a reasoning
process very much like the scientific method. We should remember that
scientific
models are obtained in various ways, perhaps even sometimes by revelation, but,
in any case, must be checked by the procedures in the scientific method. In my
opinion, we tend to overestimate the role of reason in science and
underestimate
the role of reason in religion. Bertrand Russell, one of the greatest
mathematical
logicians said,
there is an clement of truth to be learned from the mystical way of thinking (revelation, insight, intuition) which does not seem to be obtained by any other manner
What I do wish to maintain-and it is here that the scientific method is imperative-is that insight, untested and unsupported is an insufficient guarantee of truth, in spite at the tact that much of the most important truth is first suggested by its means.8
This relationship is stated by the theologian, J. Edward Dicks, in this way,
reason can become effeeive only when it is supplied material that is given it by faith. The relation is one of reciprocity. Reason contributes as it makes a critical analysis of faiths, tests its premises, interrogates its criteria, and holds in check its tendency to resort to authority.9
Perhaps, you are not conscious of this sort of process in your own experience. It is my belief that consciously or unconsciously you use reason in some of the ways I have described. If not, as Pascal has said,
Therefore, those to whom God has imparted religion by intuition are very fortunate and justly convinced. But to those who do not have it, we can give it only by reasoning, waiting for God to give spiritual insight, without which faith is only human and useless for salvation.10
I believe that for some people, at least, reason plays an important role in coming to faith. Reason cannot lead a man to God, but it can lead him to a position where God is able to reveal himself to man. Therefore, for many reasons, I agree with J. Edward Dicks' statement that "a faith accepted by critical analysis by reason is better than a faith Goddled to avoid contact with reason."11 Also, I agree with the biochemist, Denis Alexander, that "The revelation of God in Christ is accepted because as a general model of explanation it 'fits the facts' about the human condition in a way that no other model does."12
REFERENCES
1Evcs, Howard and Ncwsom, Carroll. An Introduction to The
Foundations and Fundamental Concepts of Mathematics.
N.Y.: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1966, 305.
2Heisenberg, Werner. Physics and Beyond. N.Y.: Harper and Row, 1972, 186.
3Clark, Ronald W. Einstein: The Life and Times. World Publishing Co.,
1971, 94.
4Miller, Ed. L., ed. Classical Statements on Faith and Reason.
N.Y.: Random House, 1970, 105, 113.
5Heisenherg, 216.
6Again C. S. Lewis is helpful in the understanding of some of these problems,
in particular The Problem of Pain and also his novel Till We Have
Faces, The latter
sheds light on the paradox of justice and mercy.
7Trueblood, Elton. A Place to Stand. N.Y.: Harper and Row, 1969, 20.
8Russell Bertrand. Mysticism and Logic. London: Allen and
Unwin, Ltd., 1959, 9,
12.
9Von Crueningen, John Paul, ed. Toward a Christian Philosophy of Higher
Education. Westminster Press, 1957, 59.
10Pascal, Illaise. Pensees. 282.
11Von Crueningen. 60.
12Alexandcr, Denis. Beyond Science. N.Y.: A. J. Holman Company, 1972, 182.