Science in Christian Perspective
Integrative Strategies in a Secular Age
RONALD J. BURWELL
The King's College
Briarcliff Manor
New York 10510
From: JASA 31 (September 1979): 198-201.
The theory of secularization offered by Peter Berger suggests that the modern world is characterized by a competition among diverse ideologies each seeking to become the definer of social reality. Included in this theory is the notion that the relationships among competing ideologies operate much like economic competitors in a marketplace. Building upon the metaphor of an ideological marketplace it is possible to explain the form of the diverse proposals concerning the relationship between religion and science as arising out of competition. A typology of seven strategies is outlined which are a logical response to ideological competition. Each of the strategies is described and representative examples from the religion and science literature are cited for each strategy. Some concluding observations concerning the relationship between religion and science are offered.1
The concept of secularization may be understood as a process whereby
various aspects
of society are removed from the domination of religious symbols.2 This process
is one of the fundamental characteristics of modern society. By understanding
this process it is possible to clarify the
relationship between religion and science. The last three or four hundred years
of western civilization manifest a shift from a unified world view to
a situation
marked by a multiplicity of world views. Although this is no doubt
overly simplistic,
the fact remains that modern society reflects a
pluralistic context with a number of competing world views-none of which seems
to be able to gain hegemony. The idea that there can be competition
at the level
of thought or world view was eloquently argued by the sociologist of knowledge,
Karl Mannheim.3 The notion of competition among world views has been
incorporated
into Peter Berger's statements regarding secularization in his book The Sacred
Canopy. Developing a" cognitive minority" model of
secularization, Berger
helps delineate certain trends in religion. It is my contention that Berger's
model can help explain some of the aspects of the relationship between religion
and science.
There are at least three evident values in relating the cognitive
minority theory
of secularization to the religion-science relationship. First, Berger's theory
aids in explaining why a conflict arose in the first place. A conflict can come
about only if alternative views are put forward. Having examined the course of
thought in the Western world, Berger argues that a unified world view which was
essentially religious was reduced from a position of centrality. When
alternative
views were subsequently articulated a crisis of legitimacy was created that did
not exist before. The various competing viewpoints became locked in
combat, each
seeking to establish its right to be the sole definer of reality.
Second, by building
upon the foundation of a sociology of knowledge, Berger's theory requires that
all knowledge, including science, must be conceived of as
ideological. This makes
it easier to understand why it should be presented as a competing alternative
for a religious world view. Third, having set forth a model of competing world
views, Berger argues that an ideological marketplace exists in the
modern world.4
Drawing upon economic analogies he proceeds to show how competing world views
might logically develop certain strategies in order to win converts to a world
view or to avoid the negative consequences of competition. For
example, competition
may provoke the competitors to call a truce and agree to stay out of
each other's
territory [e.g., complementary spheres of activity]. Again,
competition may encourage
the competitors to show that they have everything the competition has to offer
and thus can be selected with confidence [e.g., homogeneity of
product]. Another
response to competition is to form alliances with one's competitors in order to
secure an edge in the marketplace [e.g., çartelization or
hybridization].
Finally, competition may cause one to change a name but retain essentially the
same product [e.g., co-optation].5
Taking this understanding gained from Berger as a starting place, it
is possible
to construct a typology of the various strategies that have been used to relate
religion and science. While some strategies have been used more
extensively than
others, it is possible to sort much of the voluminous "religion
and science"
literature into seven proposed categories. A brief summary of each of
the strategies
and some problems associated with each are as follows:
Problem Solving
This approach assumes that if one or more problems currently preventing harmony
between religion and science can be solved, then the two areas could exist at
peace with one another. It seems that many of the earlier attempts at
It is possible to construct a typology of the various strategies that have been used to relate religion and science.
resolving the conflict were aimed at solving specific problems. For
example, some
felt that if only the issue of creation versus evolution could be resolved then
the conflict would disappear. Others cited problems such as freedom
and determinism.6
The difficulty with this position is that the list of problems is
seemingly inexhaustible.
Furthermore, there is a gross failure to understand that the conflict
is not merely
at the empirical level but rather at the philosophical level.
Attitude Change
Fundamental to this strategy is the belief that the conflict between religion
and science is largely the result of exaggerated claims on the part
of scientists
and proponents of religion. The stress is upon a shift in attitudes
towards greater
humility and less doctrinaire rejection of other realms of knowledge.
Furthermore,
by realizing the limits of scientific and religious knowledge, the respective
parties might reduce the knowledge claims that are put forward.
In some ways there is an affinity between this viewpoint and another
strategy-namely,
that of complementarity. However, if the issue of attitude change is stressed
it is possible to see those arguing in this manner as constituting a distinct
position. Robert Millikan typified this approach when he argued for an attitude
of humility, which, if adhered to, would solve much of the conflict
between religion
and science:
Physics, however, has recently learned its lesson, and it has at the present moment something to teach to both philosophy and religion, namely, the lesson of not taking itself too seriously, not imagining that the human mind yet understands, or has made more than the barest beginning toward understanding the universe.7
Complementarity
There have been many discussions of the relationship between religion
and science
that have made use of a complementarity motif. The approach basically
argues for
a separation of science and religion into two realms. Some conceive of this as
a separation into equal but wholly different spheres that can have no
relationship.8
Other complementarity schemes argue for a hierarchical arrangement with certain
areas of thought nesting within other areas of thought.9 While there
is a certain
validity to the view that religion and science are different entities
with different
languages, concerns, methods and so on, a number of writers have
raised questions
concerning the validity and usefulness of such an approach.10 Implicit in
the complementarian view is a model that sees science as existing apart from an
integrated world view. In fact, if recent philosophy of science has taught us
anything it has shown us that science does not exist in a vacuum. It is culture
bound, it is theory bound, it is paradigm bound, and it is intrinsically united
to a world view. I would argue that
science is as much ideological as is religion in the sense of
ideology as understood
by the sociologist of knowledge.11 Hence, to the extent to which religion
permeates a world view, it must also permeate science.
Furthermore, complementarian strategies face the same problem as that
of attitude
change strategies. What happens when science and religion offer contradictory
propositions concerning truth? What criteria will be used to select between the
two? Does one look within one or the other domain for such criteria or must a
meta-level be constructed that will aid in selecting what propositions will be
accepted? The tendency arising out of this approach is to develop a religious
schizophrenia. Religion is placed in a separate compartment isolated from the
rest of life. An impenetrable concrete-like barrier is interposed
between religion
and other fields.
Finally, the existence of parallel explanatory systems raises the
issue of parsimony.
12 If both systems refer to the same phenomena might not one of the
explanations
be rejected as superfluous? Again, criteria must be adduced to
validate the need
for parallel explanations.
Privatization
A variant of the complementarian strategy that merits separate attention is the
privatization approach. This deals with the conflict between religion
and science
by withdrawing religion into the inner world of the self. As long as religion
offers propositions extending beyond the personal to the objective
world conflict
can occur. However, if religion becomes my personal, noncognitive,
emotional experiences
there is no need for science to conflict with that realm.13 The
difficulty with
this increasingly attractive option is that the possibility for institutional
religion and a religious community is undermined. Furthermore, truth
testing becomes
an extremely difficult operation under this strategy. What data can be brought
to bear upon the truthfulness of religious conceptions? It is
difficult to offer
such tests if religion is sealed off.
Hybridization
As in the economic realm, competition among ideologies may result in the union
of the competing elements. Hence, it is not surprising that one ploy
in the religion
and science debate has been an attempt to unite religion and science. Usually,
this has been carried out by some kind of accommodation or
redefinition of either
religion or science. John Dewey attempted to bring about a
rapproachement between
religion and science by creating a hybrid-a new kind of religion. In
part he argued
that:
... were we to admit that there is but one method for ascertaining fact and truth-that conveyed by the word 'scientific" in its most general and generous sense-no discovery in any branch of knowledge and inquiry could then disturb the faith that is religious. t should describe this faith as the unification of the self through allegiance to inclusive ideal ends, which imagination presents to us and to which the human will responds at worthy of controlling our desires and choices.14
A major difficulty with this approach is that a true hybrid is rarely formed.
Usually religion is drastically modified so that it can be fitted together with
science. When this occurs the strategy becomes one approximating
co-optation with
science absorbing religion within itself.
Equation
Related to the strategy of hybridization is the approach that
identifies religion
and science as basically the same phenomenon. This has taken several forms. In
some cases both religion and science are depicted as pursuing a
common goal (e.g.,
truth seeking). In other cases attempts are made to show that science
is basically
like a religion or that religion is science-like.15
Some of these discussions have been helpful in regaining a sense of
how both religion
and science are human enterprises and share many similarities. This has aided
in correcting the specious image of a homo scien tificus who operates
apart from
the normal human socio-cultural processes. Yet, by showing similarity
the conflict
may still not be, resolved. The most that may be concluded is that science and
religion are integral human activities-neither of which can be eliminated.
It is not enough to say that the Christian viewpoint is one among several equally appealing alternatives. To do so reduces the matter to an arbitrary selection resembling a game of chance.
Co-optation
A more sinister alternative to hybridization or equation has been the
co-optation
of religion by science or vice-versa. In other words, the conflict is resolved
by translating religion into scientific symbols. '6 One of the two
realms is extinguished
under the guise of a shift in symbols.16 This, no doubt, solves the conflict but
it does so without retaining the integrity of either science or religion.
Some Future Possibilities
These various strategies are understandable in light of Berger's model
of a competitive
ideological marketplace. The respective viewpoints of religion and science vie
for public acceptance as the interpreter of reality. Competition may result in
one view gaining ascendency (co-optation); a division of territory (complementarity, privatization); move
ment towards similarity or unity (homogeneity, hybridization, equation) or an
attempt at an uneasy truce (problem solving, attitude change). None
of these strategies
seems to be without problems. The question arises as to whether yet
another strategy
can be constructed. While I am not inclined to put forward a new
proposal, several
observations seem appropriate to the solution of the conflict between religion
and science.
First, if science is understood as being intimately tied to a world view then
it is evident that the issues cannot be resolved on the level of empirical data
alone. It will be necessary to deal philosophically with the
relationship between
religion and science. In a Christian world view this may involve an
elaboration of the data of science and Scripture within the framework of that
world view. What is the nature of reality? How does one know? What is
the nature
of man? Using this world view as a selector it may be possible to
decide between
scientific explanations that are congruent with Christian revelation and those
that are not, between explanations that may be useful but not
comprehensive, and
between explanations that are logically sound and those which are not.17 The approach
to religion and science that simply pleads for tolerance or that scurries about
on an ad hoc basis from one specific problem to another is doomed to
failure because
it does not reach down to the foundational level.
Second, attempts at solving the conflict between religion and science
that accommodate
religion to science without a sense of the validity and integrity of religion
are ultimately self defeating. If carried to its extreme this approach reduces
religion to something indistinguishable from ethics or morality. From
a Christian
perspective any attempt to relate science to Christianity must
respect the truth
statements proposed in Christian revelation. For example,
Christianity does imply
certain positions regarding the nature of man. Integration can occur
only if this
perspective is retained. Hence, any attempt to reduce Christianity to
a non-cognitive,
emotive level may solve the conflict but only at too high a cost.
Third, if the modern situation is accurately depicted as a
competitive ideological
marketplace, then the selection of one world view must be
accomplished on a rational
basis rather than a traditional basis. If Christianity is to offer a
viable world
view to the modern milieu it is imperative that attempts be made to show that
the Christian view is superior to alternative viewpoints. Reasons
need to be ad
duced to show why a Christian world view is necessary for a true understanding
of human behavior (to cite only one example), while also showing that
alternative
views without the Christian perspective fail or are less than adequate. It is
not enough to say that the Christian viewpoint is one among several appealing
alternatives. To do so reduces the matter to an arbitrary selection resembling
a game of chance.
REFERENCES
1This paper it a revised version of a paper read at the 1976 Annual Meeting of
the American Scientific Affiliation held at Wheaton College in
August. 1976.
2This definition of secularization is borrowed from Peter Berger, The
Sacred Canopy
(New York: Doubleday, 1967), p. 107. This paper is heavily dependent upon the
ideas developed by Peter Berger. For a more detailed discussion of
some of these
ideas see: Ronald J. Burwell, "Religion and the Social Sciences: A Study
of Their Relationships as Set Forth in the Terry Lectures:
19241971,'' unpublished
dissertation for the Ph.D., New York University, 1976.
3Karl Mannheim, "Competition as a Cultural Phenomenon," in Kurt
Wolff
(ed.), From Karl Mannheim (New York: Oxford, 1971), pp. 223-261.
4Peter Berger, ''A Market Model for the Analysis of Eeumenicity,"
Social
Research, XXX, 1, (Spring 1963), pp. 77-93.
5Ibid.
6Certainly many of the articles that have appeared in the Journal of
the American Scientific Affiliation might fit this category. Further examples
might be Arthur H. Compton, The Freedom of Man (New Haven: Yale
University Press,
1935); and Henry M. Russell, Fate and Freedom (New Haven: Yale
University Press,
1927).
7Robert A. Millikan, Evolution in Science and Religion (New Haven:
Yale University
Press, 1935), p. 93.
8Karl Helm, Christian Faith and Natural Science (New York: Hasper and
Row, 1953).
9Donald MacKay, The Clockwork Image (Downers Grove, Ill.: Inter Varsity Press,
1974).
10The dialogue represented in the exchange of letters and articles by John
Cramer and Donald MacKay in the pages of the Journal ASA is one indication of
the problems that exist: John A. Cramer and Donald MacKay, "The Clockwork
Image Controversy," Journal of the American Scientific Affiliation, 28,3,
(September 1976), pp. 123-127. Several papers given at the 1976
Annual ASA meeting
at Wheaton College also raised some problems: Jack Haas, "Complementarity
and Christian Thought-An Assessment"; and James E. Martin,
"Interpretive
vs. Generative Science." A recent discussion of the ideas of Donald MacKay
also reflects some of the uneasiness many have with the
complementarian approach:
Clifton J. Orlebeke, "Donald MacKay's Philosophy of
Science," Christian
Scholar's Review (Summer 1977), pp. 51-63.
11Karl Mannheim describes ideology as the notion that: ". . . opinions, statements, propositions, and systems of ideas are not taken
at their face
value but are interpreted in the light of the life situation of the
one who expresses
them. It signifies further that the specific character and
life-situation of the
subject influence his opinions, perceptions and
interpretations." Karl Mennheim,
Ideology and Utopia (New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, Inc.,
1936), p. 56.
12The issue of parsimony was raised in the dialogue between John
Cramer and Donald
MacKay cited above.
13Robert N. Bellah, "Christianity and Symbolic Realism." Journal
for
the Scientific Study of Religion, 9 (Summer 1970), pp. 89-96.
14John Dewey, A Common Faith (New Haven: Yale University Frets, 1960),
p. 32.
15A significant example of this type of argument is Langdon Gilkey, Religion
and the Scientific Future (New York: Harper and Row, 1970).
16This may take the form of a "sociologizasion of religion" or a
"psychologization of religion." See: Berger, The Sacred Canopy, pp.
166-169.
17Recently Nicholas Wolterstorff has argued that a person's Christian world view
should operate as a selector when confronting diverse theoretical
options: Nicholas Wolterstorff, Reason Within the Bounds of Religion (Grand Rapids:
Eerdman's, 1976).