Science in Christian Perspective
Science and Religion:
Is Compatibility Possible?
DON WIEBE
Department of Religious Studies
University of Manitoba
Winnipeg, Manitoba,
Canada
From: JASA 30 (December
1978): 169-176.
Compatibility Systems
To raise the question of the possible compatibility' of science and religion
must, in the light of the historical relations of the scientific
and religious
communities, seem utterly naive. Since the days of Galileo and Urban VIII, it
can he argued, the image of conflict has appropriately dominated
all discussion
of the relation of religion to science. The dominant picture, as
Andrew White's
famous History of the Warfare Between Science and Theology (1896) illustrates
(although somewhat onesidedly), has been one of the religious
faithful fighting
the progress of the sciences, particularly when new discoveries
threatened the
security of cherished dogmas. And today the image of conflict is reinforced,
despite the fact that contemporary scientific beliefs are more congenial to
religious (and especially Christian) doctrines than those of a few
generations ago,1 for the conflict, it is maintained, is basically methodological. Both
science and religion, that is, seem to be playing the
"cognition game"
and yet religion, so it is claimed, seems to follow an entirely different set
of rules in its achievement of "knowledge" than does science.2 The
point of the modern view of the conflict image, then, is that
science provides
us with a clear and straightforward paradigm for knowing-a "morality of
knowledge3-which religious thinking obviously contravenes.
Despite such
claims, however, there is a reluctance on the part of many to
accept the image
of conflict as an appropriate category in discussion of the
relations of science
and religion, for both science and religion have made valued contributions to
our lives and neither is likely to wither away in the very near future. That
reluctance to deny the valise of either community has inspired
alternative interpretations
of the meanings of science and religion that "entail"
compatibility.
And it is the variety and significance of these various "compatibility
systems" that I wish to look at in this paper.
A "compatibility system" is essentially a justification
of accepting
two apparently conflicting systems of thought.4 If a prima facie conflict
existed there would
be no impetus to construct such a system. The growth of science in the West,
however, with the gradual "disenchantment' of the universe
attendant upon
that growth (i.e. the increasing superfluity of religious hypotheses in the
attempts to account for or describe the world) suggests a radical
discontinuity
between science and religion-it suggests, in fact, that to do proper science
one must give up religion. Such a "conflict interpretation" of the
relation of religion to science rests on two assumptions: first, that science
alone provides us with the paradigm of all knowledge-gaining procedures and,
second, that religion is correctly or appropriately characterized, at least
in part, as a system of beliefs. Compatibility proposals, consequently, rest
on challenges to either one or both of these assumptions.
I shall look briefly at four kinds of compatibility proposals here:5 (1) science
and religion are wholly incommensurable; (2) science and religion
are complementary
but provide us with radically different kinds of knowledge; (3) science and
religion are complementary because science itself reveals elements
of ultimacy
and, consequently, exhibits a religious character; and (4) science
and religion
are complementary because archaic systems contain genuine cognitive insights
although they need to he re-expressed in terms of contemporary
scientific thought.
The classic "compatibility system"-namely, that science
and religion
are complementary because they are logically similar
"enterprises"-however,
challenges neither of the major assumptions of the conflict interpretation.
Accepting both assumptions it nevertheless differs drastically upon
their interpretation:
science, it agrees, provides us with a "morality of knowing" but it
hotly disputes the nature or significance of that morality.
Extending the metaphor,
one might say that the compatibility argument here does not involve
the denial
of an ethic of belief but rather suggests that the ethic is a contextual or
situational one rather than an absolutist ethic. That is to say,
just as ethical
judgment is more than mere "ethical calculation" so knowing is
more than mere logical or "epistemic calculation." I
consider briefly
the merits of this claim following the description of the
above-mentioned alternatives.
Science and Religion as Wholly Incommensurable
Many philosophers reject the conflict interpretation in the
discussion of science
and religion because, according to them science and religion are
incommensurable;
they are incapable of even being compared. Thus religion cannot be
either compatible
or incompatible with science; nor can it complement science in the sense of
providing a different or higher' kind of knowledge that science
cannot achieve.
The assumption that religion is appropriately characterized as knowledge or
as a system of beliefs, it is argued, reveals a naive understanding
of religion.
Religion is a "way of life" and not a source of knowledge. Religion
functions in society in a different capacity altogether than
science-it grounds
the meaning of human existence. Religious language, therefore, is
not the language
of knowing but rather the language of commitment (Braithwaite, 1955); it is
parabolic (Miles, 1959), self-involving (Evans, 1963; 1968),
convictional (Zuurdeeg,
1959), symbolic (Randall, 1958), etc., but not epistemic. T. R. Miles neatly
summarizes the essential point of this position in his Religion and
the Scientific
Outlook as follows:
On the general question of a conflict between science and religion there is
a central part of the problem which we can safely clams to have settled once
for all. This claim is not the presumptuous one that it sounds, for
she matter
is one of logical necessity and it would be muddled thinking to
claim anything
less. Religions language is of many different kinds; there is the language of
parable, the language of moral exhortation, the language of worship
and so on.
Only if what is offered in the name. of religion is factual
assertion can there
be any possibility of a hcadnn conflict . . . . To insist that such
(religions)
language is parable and not literal truth is to ascribe a
recognizable and legitimate
function to a group of basic religious assertions and the result is to supply
a permanent guarantee that these assertions cannot he refuted by the findings
of science. (Miles, 1959; 217, 218, 219).
Science and Religion as Providing Radically Different Kinds of Knowledge
Proponents of this kind of compatibility systems do not deny that
in some respects
religion and science are incommcnsurablc. They deny that science is the only
paradigm for all knowledgegaining procedures and so admit that
science and religion
are methdologicallv incommensurable. By suspending belief in the
first assumption
of the incompatibility thesis, they insist, it can be shown that
there are non-scientific
ways of knowing-ways of knowing that transcend and so complement the knowledge
of science. Karl Heim sets forth a persuasive argument in support of such a
thesis in his Christian Faith and Natural Science (1953).
According to Heim existentialism has discovered a whole new world
of nonobjective
experience. Consequently it opens up the possibility of a knowledge
of a nonobjective
space that is wholly other than the knowledge of the objective space of the
natural sciences. Heim calls this first nonobjective space
"egospace,"
for it is first discovered in the discovery of the
inner Self-in the inward awareness of one's Self.
New spaces, according to Heim, are discovered when they make
possible something
which is undeniable in our experience, although within the space or
spaces thus
far discovered it appears self-contradictory. The (inner) Self which must, in
the light of our experience, be part of our general picture of the universe
is, for example, invisible in the objective space of the natural sciences but
becomes 'visible" in the non-objective ego-space.
Still others spaces, according to Heim, are revealed when questions of ethics
and origins are raised. We find in these issues that what is necessary for a
comprehensive picture of the universe is in the objective space of
the natural
sciences (as well as in the egospace, for both these spaces are
species of the
genus "polar-space") problematic. For example, in the
area of ethical
action the ego is paralyzed by the relativism and positivism that
characterises
all our decision-making. Within the "polar-spaces" no
goals are absolute
except those chosen by the human will. Consequently action is hound either by
indecision as to which goal to direct one's action toward, or it is plagued
by the sense of arbitrariness in the goal chosen. What is needed, therefore,
is a new space wherein both the indecision and arbitrariness can he avoided
since both undermine the ethical life. Such a possibility, Heim insists, can
he seen only in "suprapolar space:"
Unlike all human ethical doctrines, which are historically and
culturally conditioned
and possess only limited validity, Christ, according to the conviction of the
primitive church, is the Kyrios, the only one entitled to the name which is
above all names, the supreme authority, above which there is no higher power
and by which the final decision is taken with regard to every value
that comes
within our field of vision-the supreme yardstick by which all
things are measured.
This authority is like the lighthouse by which ships may steer their course
when they have to pass by night through a dangerous channel which is full of
rocks. If such a paramount authority is found to exist, then the
aim of positivism
too is achieved, for positivism seeks a supreme value, the
antecedents of which
do not require investigations. (Heim, 1953; 190, 191).
The Universe, then, consists of spaces rather than merely objective space as
is assumed in the secular philosophies. Knowledge of the other
spaces, particularly
of the "supra-polar space," however, cannot come via reasoning or
thinking which find their chief application in objective space-one
simply becomes
(or does not become) aware of such nonobjective spaces:
. . we are not ourselves able to force open the gate which leads to
a space that has so far been closed to us. Whenever we experience
the discovery
of a space, the
discovery always simply falls into our laps as a gift ... (Heim,
1953; 170)
From the standpoint of the polar spaces this experience is totally
incomprehensible
(Heim, 1953; 192). That knowledge comes, then, by revelation-the scales must
fall from one's eyes before one is able to "see" it. Consequently
faith is the condition in which the person who lives completely immersed in
this stsprapolar space finds himself. He has the same security and confidence
as does the secularist who lives wholly within the polar spaces.
This is a kind of two-level theory of knowledge
(truth) and as \1. Diamond points out in his Contemporary
Philosophy and Religious
Thought (1974) it "is the major strategy of religious existentialists in
coping with the challenges of a scientifically oriented
culture." (p. 303)
Other similar compatibility proposals, as Diamond points out, can he found in
Buher, Bultmann, Barth, and Tillich. The classic statement of this school of
thought, perhaps, is to he found in Kierkegaard's Concluding
Unscientific Postscript
(1941), in his talk of "truth as subjectivity." Of kindred mind is
Pascal's reference to the reasons of the heart that reason knows
nothing of.
In all such two-level theories, as Diamond points out, a
compatibility and complementarity
between the lower and higher levels of truth is claimed but, at the
same time,
a greater importance is claimed for the higher (or religious) level
of knowledge
and truth.
Science and Religion as Complementary Because Science Is Very Much
Like Religion
Stated somewhat crudely, compatibility systems of
this order claim to show that science functions not only in a
cognitive capacity
but also, ;,.though in an inferior way, in a religious one; that is, science
is a kind of religion surrogate. Langdon Gilkey's Religion and the Scientific
Future (1970) is an apologetic of this kind. Although "secular man"
believes one thing-namely, that he is irreligious-his existence,
claims Gilkey,
reveals a dependence on elements of ultimacy. Gilkey makes this
point in a broad
and general way in his Naming the Whirlwind (1969) but here points up three
specific characteristics of ultimacy in Science.6 The first, he insists, is
found in the unremitting eros to know. Further, the assumptions of
some ontological
generality about the character of reality as such and of the possibility of
a relationship between it and the knowing mind is a leap beyond the
evidence-it
is a step beyond the bounds of science to that which ultimately makes sense
of the scientific enterprise ill the first place. The third hint of ultimacy
in science, he claims, is to be found in the structure of
scientific judgment,
a structure that reveals, in the final analysis, the ultimate
awareness of oneself
as knower. In this regard he writes;
(The) personal affirmation of oneself as a knower is the foundation
of the possibility
of all rational judgment and in the end it grounds all science. In turn this
awareness of oneself as a knower cannot be doubted. The sceptic,
in affirming
his scepticism also is aware of himself and affirms himself as understanding
the view that he now asserts; he is also aware of himself as
fudging that this
view is in tact true . . . . No movement could take place without
this element
of indubitable certainty, without this unconditioned assertion of
the actuality
of knowing ourselves. (Gilkey, 1970; 60, 61).
According to Gilkey, then, modern man's science and trust in science results
in the adoption of a new niytba quasi-religions myth-which he calls
the "myth
of total awareness." The myth asserts that
man becomes man and can control his life and destiny if he is
educated, liberal,
analyzed, scientific, an 'ex
pert', etc . that knowledge and awareness can turn
whatever has been a blindly determining force on and in man and so
a fate over
nsau, into a new instrument of man. ) Gilkey, 1970; 77)
Religions do make empirically significant claims and so can conflict with science.
The emergence of the myth, Gilkey claims, shows man's need for
'intimaey"
and an attempt on the part of science itself to fulfill that need after having
contributed to the loss of ultimacy in contributing to the decline
or "demise"
of religion.7 Gilkey sees the new myth, however, as dangerous,
for, according
to him science and technology which are to he the source of man's salvation
(according to the new myth) are in actuality the source of the
threat to man's
ultimate well-being. (Gilkey, 1970; 92, 95). Science, therefore,
"reaches
out for" ultimacy yet is unable within itself to provide it.
Consequently
science requires religion-religion however that goes beyond the "broken
images" of past tradition. Thus Giikey concludes;
The dilemmas of even the most secular of cultures are ultimately intelligible
only in the light of faith; the destiny of even a scientific world
can be adequately
thematized only in terms of religious symbols; and the confidence
of the future
even of technological man can be creatively grounded only if the coming work
of the Lord in she affairs of men is known and affirmed. (Gilkey,
1970; 99)
Science and Religion as Compatible Because There
Are Genuine Cognitive Insights in Archaic
Religious Systems
Compatibility systems 0f this sort attempt to salvage the
folk-wisdom of archaic
cultures. Philosophers admit that there is a radical methodological
incompatibility
between the hun-that religion has gained its insights in
"unacceptable"
ways-hut attempts' also to point out that, somehow or other,
insights of importance
to man were obtained. Thus religion can complement science in a cognitive way
(although only heuristically so), but its insights will require the services
of a "translator"-the insights, that is, require support in terms
of a scientific justification. B. Burhoe's aim in his "The Concepts of
God and Soul in a Scientific View of Human Purpose" (1973) contains the
germ of this kind of compatibility system. He writes;
I seek . . . in this paper to show how belief in a reality sovereign over man
(a god) and a belief in the essential immortality or eternal
duration of man's
basic nature (a soul) not only are necessary for human motivation
but are indeed
credible on the very grounds of science, which confirms insights
common to the
higher
religious traditions of the world . I think in the
modern sciences we have far surpassed earlier methods by which man
finds knowledge.
However, I have already pointed out that the scientific method does not shut)
looking into and taking advantage of more ancient accumulations of
wisdom such
as the genetic 'wisdom of the body', or the traditional wisdom of
human cultures. Burhoe, 1973; 416, 417).
Science And Religion As Logically Similar Enterprises
This, the boldest of the compatibility systems, lays claim to a complementary
relationship between science and religion on the basis of a logical
similarity
between the two communities on the basis of the claim, that is,
that religion, like science, has cognitive significance and that its claims
to knowledge have the same "foundation' as the claims to
knowledge by science.
Like the proponents of the conflict thesis, the exponents of this
understanding
of science and religion assume both that religion is appropriately
characterized,
at least in part, as a system of beliefs and that science provides
us with the
paradigm for our knowledge-gaining procedures or activities.
However, although
agreeing that the "morality of knowledge" that governs activity in
the sciences has full sway in theology or "reflective religion," it
differs radically with the conflict theorists on the interpretation
or description
of that morality.
The indictment by the rationalist is that the recourse to faith by
the religious
believer in his "religious knowing" permits him to evade the force
of the standards and canons of rational assessment which he himself
recognizes
to be binding in other areas of cognitive concern, such as, for
example, history8
or the natural sciences.9 This, the rationalist insists, corrodes
the "machinery"
of coming to a sound judgment whereby truth might be separated from falsehood
and so calls "into question the very conception of scientific thought as
a responsible enterprise of reasonable men." (Scheffler, 1967; v). It is
assumed, therefore, that science can prove its knowledge claims (i.e. justify
them),"10 while religion cannot. Scientific method, therefore,
can provide
impersonal, objective and hence reliable knowledge while the non-scientific
"disciplines," and religion iii particular, can provide
us with mere
opinion, or, at best, illuminating visions.11 In science there is a
convergence
of belief which one fails to obtain in religious matters, for
"belief"
(knowledge?) in science is a matter of evidential appraisal and
logical assessment,
whereas "belief" in religion depends upon persuasion and rhetoric
aimed at conversion-that is, it is based upon extra-logical and
non-evidential
bases. The adoption of religious beliefs or a change of religious
beliefs, consequently,
is a matter of intuition and is, in some sense then, a mystical and
subjective
affair, a matter for psychological description only. But the adoption of new
scientific theories, or a change of scientific belief, is a matter
of proceeding
according to strict logical and methodological rules.
Such a view of science and scientific rationality, it is argued, however, is
naive. The dominant attitude which distinguishes scientific
thinking as presenting
us with objective knowledge from nonscientific thinking which is emotive or
cognative is fundamentally wrongheaded. It is so, however, not
because religious
thinking resembles scientific thinking in its logical rigor but
rather because
scientific thinking is a good deal less rigorous than it is
generally supposed
and hence that it is in some respects like religious thinking. 12 The rules
of logic and/or evidence that have been suggested as characterizing
scientific
thought as wholly rational, it is claimed, cannot account adequately either
for the existence of our knowledge or its growth. Such an account
can be provided
only if science itself is seen as a "fiduciary" enterprise-i.e. as
involving personal judgment (fiducia, trust/faith) that of necessity exceeds
the grounds of evidence from which it first arose. Since purely
logical procedures
or evidential appraisal cannot "guarantee" one's conclusions, it is
"wrong" to place the
responsibility for their acceptance upon a set of external rules.13
The acceptance
not only of specific scientific conclusions, therefore, but even
the so-called
rules of scientific procedure involve an element of
"faith" in their adoption.
This kind of attempt at establishing that science and religion are compatible
is extremely common. Historically, however, the claim was that religion was
structurally similar to science and now the claim is that science
is structurally
similar to religion. The position is adequately represented today, I think,
in H, K. Schilling's Science and Religion: An Interpretation of Two
Communities.
According to Schilling each of the communities constitutes a kind
of enterprise
concerned with (1) (an empirical or factual) description of the universe; (2)
an explanation or theoretical account of the universe; and (3) a
transformation
of human existence in the universe (i.e. with an application of the insights
achieved). After analysis of each of these concerns within each of
the communities
he concludes:
out of this analysis emerges the idea of a continuous spectrum of cognition
and knowledge, extending from the physical sciences, through biological and
social sciences, through the arts to religion. It is proposed that
some characteristics
of knowledge and of the cognitive process vary continuously within
the spectrum
from one end to the other, but that others remain constant. Thus we can speak
of 'knowledge' in all these fields and assert that in an important sense the
way it is attained is the same for all of them. There is therefore
no discontinuous
separation of science and religion as far as cognition is
concerned. (Schilling,
1963).
Similar theses are maintained by C. Coulson in his
Science and Christian Beliefs (1955; see also his 1969);
by I. Ramsey in his Religion and Science: Conflict and Synthesis (1964); by
I. Barbour in his Issues in Science and Religion (1966); as well as by a host
of others.
The Science of Religion
The majority of the compatibility proposals of the past have been concerned
largely with reducing the tension (doctrinal and methodological)
between religion
and the natural sciences. With the increasing attention that the
social sciences
have received in recent years the question of compatibility has been further
complicated-particularly in respect to the science and/or sciences
of religion.
The social sciences in providing us with a knowledge about ourselves and the
world around us, provide us also with a scientific knowledge of
religion. Religion
itself is an object of study and consideration by science. Consequently one
has two views of religion to consider when talking of the relations
of science
and religion-that of the insider, the committed believer, and that
of the outsider,
in this case the objective scientist revealing to us the truth
about religion.
Compatibility as it has been discussed above hardly seems a possibility now,
it would seem, for the scientific view of religion requires the adoption of
assumptions inimical to religion. Sociologists, for example,
maintain that the
study of religion can he undertaken only insofar as it is a cultural system
and not treated as a divine or supernatural institution.14 As one sociologist
puts it, a scientific understanding of religion presupposes a
"methodological
atheism."15 And
another writes:
Science inevitably takes a naturalistic view of religion. This is a necessary
assumption not a demonstrated truth from which all science proceeds. Religion
is in man; it is to he understood by the analysis of his needs,
tendencies and
potentialities . . . . For those who identify religion with
supernatural views
of the world it must appear that scientific analysis must weaken religion.22
(Yinger, 1970; 531).
Yinger assumes here, as did Durkheim, that
That which science refuses to grant to religion is not its right to
exist, but
its right to dogmatize upon the nature of things and the special competence
which it claims for itself for knowing man and the world. As a matter of fact
[Durkheim goes on to say] it does not know what it is made of, nor
to what need
it answers. (Durkheim, 1971; 430)
Religion properly (i.e. scientifically) understood, therefore, is real and is
compatible with science. Religion and science, that is, are compatible since
they are coexistent realities, but there is no compatibility
between religion's
understanding of itself and the social-scientific understanding of religion
(and, consequently, none between the religious view of the world
and the scientific-physical
and chemical view of the world.) To quote Yinger again:
Science disproves religious beliefs, but it does not disprove religion. There
may be conflict between science and a given religion, if part of
its total system
is a series of propositions about the nature of the world, but
there is no general
conflict between science and religion defined in functional terms. (Yinger,
1970; 61. See also pp. 93, 94).
The compatibility systems discussed above seem to he undermined by the claims
of the social scientists. At first it might seem that the incommensurability
thesis remains "undamaged" but the judgment is mistaken,
for although
the two communities are indeed incommensurable there is no doubt in the mind
of the social scientist that science is the superior community. The value of
religion, that is, is revealed by science-a conclusion far removed from the
claims of the incommensurability supporters of the religious camp (e.g. T. R.
Miles). It would seem, therefore, that even though the conflict
thesis is only
weakly supported in the contrast between religion and the natural sciences it
is thoroughly extablished in the contrast between religion and the
social sciences.
Two important questions need to he raised with respect to the social sciences
and the science of religion in particular. The first concerns the descriptive
sciences and especially the phenomenology of religion. It is
important to know
precisely the nature and structure of the historical religious
traditions. The
study of the various religious traditions show them to be very much concerned
with a knowledge of the world, both mundane and soperinuodane. In
the religious
traditions of Judaism, Christianity and Islam, for example, the
belief element
is of considerable importance and has, in good measure, accounted
for the force
and power those traditions hold in the world today.16 It is a fact
then (revealed
by a phenomenological study of religion) that religion consciously provides,
or attempts to provide, explanations of the world .17 Moreover,
they are cognizant
of the possible conflict between their explanations and those provided by the
sciences and have developed compatibility systems to overcome or mitigate the
conflict. To simply ignore this primary cognitive interest of
religion is simply
not acceptable-it is to overlook one of the key elements of the
major religious
traditions.
The second major question that needs to be raised concerns the methodological
assumptions of the social sciences-in particular the assumption of atheism as
it is enunciated, for example, by F. Berger (1961; 1963; 1967; 1971), It is
impossible, it seems, to distinguish Berger's "methodological
atheism"
from atheism tout caort. Such an atheistic (naturalistic)
assumption is really
a theological assumption, although in a negative mode, that is no
more acceptable
than the theological bias of the religiously committed person:
either assumption
introduces "distortion" in the study of the data.18 Smart
brings the
point out clearly when he writes;
it happens that the dominant theories in sociology have allowed at
most a partial
autonomy to religion itself; and this may be a justifiable
conclusion. However,
it is not at all clear that the whole question of autonomy has been
dealt with
in a proper manner . . . . It has not been easy for the human
sciences outside
religion to rid themselves of an explicitly theological Discipline. (Smart,
1973; 22, 23)
The conclusions about religion reached by the social scientist,
therefore, have
no more inherent validity than do the conclusions reached by the
critical study
of the religiously committed. Consequently the supposed conflict
between religion's
self-understanding and the social scientific understanding of religion is not
automatically resolved in favour of the social sciences.
A Renewed Understanding
The proliferation of compatibility systems suggests the emergence
of a renewed
understanding of both the scientific and religious communities. None of the
systems, I think, is without flaw. All of them are helpful in one
way or another,
although some only negatively so in that they force us to
re-examine old assumptions
and presuppositions about religion and/or science. It is obvious,
for example,
that the early "skirmishes" over cognitive matters
between the scientific
and religious communities led to a hardening of the lines of
opposition in which
those in the religious community seemed to forget that religion is a matter
of life and not only a matter of cognition-that religion is a
matter of existential
decision and commitment and not merely a matter of knowing the
nature and structure
of the universe. Furthermore, science, encouraged by its early victories in
such "skirmishes," came to see itself as a wholly
rational enterprise
which could easily he broadened to include all of life-to apply to
every aspect
of human existence. The noncognitivist systems of com
patibility with their emphasis upon the moral/emotional aspect of religion
function, then, to place limitations on this scientific
(scientistic?) rationalization
of human existence.
Insofar as religion is not logical or epistemic calculation it has something
to contribute to life that science does not possess. By denying
cognitive import
to religion, therefore, the noncognitivist avoids debate with the sciences
and reveals
the enriching effect that religion can have for man and society. The claim on
the part of the scientific community to have no need of such enrichment, that
is, that science would eventually rationalize or make meaningful the whole of
our existence, has really not undermined the noncogoitivist
compatibility system,
as one might suspect, but rather has further weakened the conflict
theory. Gilkey,
it will he remembered, points out that such a claim on behalf of science is
really a "mythification" of science-a substitution of the
scientific
"myth of total awareness" in place of the older religious
myths. And
in this science reveals elements of ultimacy such as characterize religion.
Gilkey's attempt at reconciling the two communities is extremely important
for
it suggests that compatibility systems may need as much scrutiny and analysis
of science as of religion, for the real nature of science has yet
to be revealed.
Too much has been assumed about the nature of science too soon. Gilkey's own
kind of compatibility proposal is not wholly adequate, however, for
his suggestion
that science needs necessarily to reach out to religious myths of
ultimacy hardly
follows from the fact that some have made of science a
quasireligious myth."
Furthermore, Gilkey fails to reveal whether this completion of science in the
(revitalized) religious myths is a cognitive completion. It seems to me that
it is not and therefore suffers the weaknesses of all
noncognitivist proposals.
The claim that religion provides us with a radically different kind
of knowledge
than that provided by science parallels the claim of the
noncognitivist in respect.
The noncognitivist completion of religion is not subject to
scientific critique
because it is "beyond" cognition. Similarly the claim to
"super-knowledge"
is beyond scientific critique for the criteria of knowledge do not apply to
the knowledge obtained in the "realization" or experience
of the Ultimate.
As one scholar puts it in criticism of those who assume all knowledge subject
to the same criteria:
What can one say of all those treatises that attempt to make the
religious doctrines
a subject of profane study, as if there were no knowledge that was
not accessible
to anyone and everybody as if it were sufficient to have been to school to be
able to understand the most venerable wisdom better than the sages understood
it themselves? For it is assumed by 'specialists' and 'critics' that there is
nothing that is beyond their powers; such an attitude resembles
that of children
who, having found books, intended for adults, judge them according to their
ignorance, caprice, and laziness. (Shuon, 1975; 8)
This kind of compatibility proposal, however, fails to recognize
that religions
make ordinary as well as extraordinary knowledge claims. Furthermore, many of
the extraordinary knowledge claims seem to have implications that hear upon
states of affairs in the world and so involve implicit knowledge claims about
the empirical world. Such beliefs can conflict with other nonreligious claims
about the world and these are not accounted for within this
compatibility system.
However, even though it is inadequate as a compatibility system, it
is nevertheless
a salutary warning against scientific arrogance. Whether or not
such superknowledge
exists cannot be proven by science but neither can science disprove
its existence.
The claim that there are genuine cognitive insights to be found its archaic
religions that are capable of being re-expressed in modern
scientific terminology
hardly constitutes a compatibility system. It suggests the
substantial or doctrinal
compatibility of science and religion-or at least the possibility
of a doctrinal
or cognitive supplement to science by religion. How this is possible-except
by happenstance-unless there is also a methodological compatibility is left
unexplained.
Cognitive Significance of Religion
A compatibility system, it seems to me, is required only if religion actually
claims cognitive significance and in particular claims knowledge of
the nature,
structure, and meaning of this world and our existence in it. If
religion makes
no cognitive claims or only purely transempirical (i.e.
supraworldly) cognitive
claims then it is in a different league altogether from scientific discourse
and can never conflict with it. But religions do make empirically significant
claims and so can conflict with science, In the history of Christian thought,
for example, there has often been a conflict of theories or views
of the world
or some particular aspect of the world. That such cognitive disagreement is
less noticeable today than in the past (i.e. less so after the overthrow of
Newtonian physics) 20 shows some possibility of a compatibility between the
two. That there is not complete agreement, and never has been, does
not preclude
that there cannot be. Scientific theories cannot be espoused as final truths
for science is progressive. Similarly religious doctrines have
often been inadequately
interpreted. Since there is less than omniscience in either of the
two communities
a complete agreement of thought between them is hardly to he expected.
Mere doctrinal agreement between science and religion is not
enough, as I have
already intimated above. The knowledge claimed by religion must be testable
or checkable in the same (general) way as is scientific knowledge.
An adequate
compatibility system, therefore, must show that religion in its
cognitive aspect
has a similar logical structure to science. In the past such proposals have
been unacceptable for they assunned the complete rationality of science and
then attempted to show religion to be as rational as science.
However, the recourse
to faith-the lack of absolute objectivity in religion-repeatedly dashed all
hopes of success in this endeavour. As I have already pointed out, however,
the procedure is now reversed due to new revelations about the
nature of scientific
thought. Crudely put, the methodological similarity is now seen to exist in
the fact that scientific thought is really as
"irrational" as theological
thought. Much philosophical analysis of science and recent history of science
seems to reveal that science is not a strictly logical and wholly empirical
affair as it was once conceived to he. The work of philosophers and
historians
such as M. Polanyl (1958), T. Kuhn (1962), P. Feyerabend (1970)
cL.al. reveals
a fiduciary character to science. 21 As Kuhn puts it, scientific thought is
characterized both by "ordinary scientific thought" and
"extraordinary
scientific thought" but only the former can be characterized as wholly
rational: a "deductive affair," Extraordinary thought does not move
in a logical step-by-step fashion but rather has the character of a
"cumulative
argument" and is, consequently very like
theological argumentation.
No Necessary Conflict
Whether science and religion are compatible, it should now he obvious, is a
question that transcends the framework of thought of both these communities.
That religion can enshrine superstitious or unfounded beliefs that can come
into conflict with scientific doctrine cannot he disputed. But that there is
a necessary and general conflict between science and religion has
nowhere been
shown. Doctrinally there have often been agreements between the two
communities.
And shifts of doctrine that bring about such agreement have not always been
made by the religious community. Further, the claim that science and religion
are radically different in method has until now been assumed on the strength
of the modern reputation of science and has never been established.
The various
compatibility' systems outlined above reveal a variety of challenges to the
claim itself, or to the significance or meaning of the claim. The claim of an
inherent and all-pervasive conflict between science and religion, I
suggest therefore,
is an assumption, not wholly groundless, but not a conclusion. The uncritical
tenacity with which it is held at times suggests, moreover, that it
is a modern
myth. That none of the compatibility proposals outlined all too briefly above
has achieved universal agreement among philosophers or even among theologians
does not make the assumption more than an assumption. The
dissolution of long-standing
myths is never likely to he the result of direct attack, but rather
the product
of a steady erosion, over a long period of time, of the uncritical
foundations
upon which they rest. The insights vis a vis science and religion gained from
the various compatibility proposals discussed hint at the groundlessness of
the conflict assumption and, as a result, suggests the possibility
of compatibility.
Indeed, a thorough analysis of the classical compatibility system to which I
have referred above will show, I think, not only the possibility of
compatibility
but also its plausibility.
NOTES
1
C.f. Mascal, (1965; 31, 32).
2
C.f. Seheffler (1967) and Hartley (1962).
3The concept of a morality of knowledge is not new. It was first used in the
last century by William Clifford (1970). The idea refers both to the intimate
connection between belief and action as well as to the act of
believing in itself.
There is the suggestion, or better claim, that there is a moral demand upon
us in all the claims we make to be as clear as possible about what we are or
are not saying and that we hold all such claims open to testing and checking
of their validity or soundness. The scientists, then, are asking
the theologians
to be as clear in these regards as they are themselves. cf. Chisholm (1956),
Harvey (1966), Lakatos (1970), et. of.
4Tlse concept is Smart's (1973; 82, 83).
5There is no suggestion here that the typology is exhaustive. There
may he other
different and more fruitful ways of interpreting she vast literature on the
subject. I have found this particular classification helpful here.
6For a similar analysis c.f. Creeley (1974).
7C.f. Cauthen (1969; 13-15, et.
passim.).
8
C.f. Harvey (1966).
9C.f. Scheffler (1967).
10By "justify" I mean here "to make acceptable." In this
sense I regard Popper's talk of falsification as a procedure for making some
claims (tentatively) acceptable. Time does
The claim of an inherent and all-pervasive conflict between science
and religion
is an assumption, not wholly groundless, but not a conclusion. Time does
not permit an analysis of Popper's claims here. I refer the reader to, inter
ala, Achinstein (1968), Thakur (1970), and Kneale (1967).
111t is assumed here that knowledge can be radically distinguished
from belief-only
the former having certitude. I have subjected this assumption to
critical analysis
elsewhere and will not repeat the argument here. Suffice it to say that I see
this distinction to be philosophically unsound;
belief and knowledge exist on the same continuum. cf. Wiebe (1974).
12Cf. Schiller (1955).
13Th is the burden of Polanyi's argument throughout his Per
sonal Knowledge: Towards a Post-rational Philosophy as well as his
other writings.
(Polanyi, 1958).
14C,f. van Baaren and Drijvers, (1973). 1C.f. Berger (1967).
16C.f. Smart (1969).
171 have dealt with the issue of religious explanation in my
"Explanation
and Theological Method" (1976).
18For further discussion of this issue see my "Is A Science of Religion
Possible?" (1978).
19A thesis similar to Gilkcy's is to be found in the works of J.
Ellul, especially
in his The Technological Society (1964) as well in P. Slater (1970, 1974) and
A. Whellis (1971,
1973). I do not, however, find myself in full agreement with the
thesis as Gilkey
frames it. According to Gilkey the myth asserts that man becomes man and can
control his destiny if he becomes properly educated and that
knowledge can change
what has been a blind determining force over man into an instrument of his.
But this is not what such advocates of the "myth" in fact proclaim.
Such a picture of the new "myth-makers," applied indiscriminately
to all philosophers of science is extremely crude. What the
"secular man"
says, it seems to me, is not that man can control his destiny but that since
there is no one else (i.e. some great magician or divinity of whom
we are aware
as controlling our destinies for our benefit) to look after man, man must, if
he is to survive, do so himself. And the best way of proceeding in this task
is to know as much as possible about the nature of the physical and
social worlds
we encounter. As Karl Popper has it (1962, 1957), to suggest that man cannot
and must not make changes and must not attempt to
"remake" the world
is to offer a very poor solution, or none at all, to the problem man faces.
It is because of advice like this that so many cry out against a
return to theology
(e.g. S. Hook, 1961; Nagel, 1961; et.al.) To be sure, control must be wielded
over the "controllers," as Gilkey puts it, but that control also is
a human control. (See here particularly the section entitled
"The Principle
of Leadership" in chapter seven of Popper's 1962). Thus
Popper, among others,
in direct contrast to Gilkey, claims on behalf of the rationalist the lofty
aim of bringing about a more reasonable world-a society that aims
at humaneness
and reasonableness; at a reduction of war, strife, etc.; at
equality and freedom;
a world in which one day "men may even become the conscious creators of
an open society, and thereby of a greater part of their fate." (Popper,
1962, Vol. 2 94). Neither the intention nor the result of rationalist action
then is, as Gilkey has depicted it, necessarily tyrannical. Its
intention, and
possibly the result as well, is to lead man from a "closed society"
in which his fate is almost totally con
trolled by others, to the open society in which the individual
comes increasingly
to direct his own fate.
20C.f. Maseal, (1965).
21Similar suggestions are to be found in R. Nash (1963); J. H. Ziman (1968);
and Errol Harris (1970).
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Achinstcin, Peter (1968). 'Review of K. R. Popper's Conjec
tures and Refutations", British Journal for the Philosophy
of Science 19, 1968.
Harbour, I. C. (1966). Issues in Science and Religion,
Prentice-Hall, 1966.
Hartley, W. W. (1962). Retreat to Commitment, A. A. Knopf, 1962.
Berger, Peter L. (1961). The Precarious Vision: An Essay on Social Perception
and Christian Faith, Doubleday, 1961.
Berger, Peter L. (1967). The Sacred Canopy: Elements of a Sociology
of Religion,
Doubleday, 1967.
Berger, Peter L. (1969). A Rumour of Angels, Penquin, 1969.
Berger, Peter L. (1971). The Social Construction of Reality,
Penquin, 1971.
Braitbwaite, R. B. (1955). An Empiricist's View of the Nature
of Religious Belief, Cambridge University Press, 1955.
Burhoc, Ralph W. (1973). "The Concepts of God and Soul in a Scientific
View of Human Purpose", Zygon, 8, 1973.
Cautben, Kenneth (1969). Science, Secularization and God,
Abingdon Press, 1969.
Chisholm, Roderick N. (1956). "Epistemic Statements and the
Ethics of Belief", Philosophy and Phenomenological Re
search, 16, 1956.
Clifford, Wm. (1970). "The Ethics of Belief" in Mavrodes, C. (ed.):
The Rationality of Belief in Cod, Prentice-Hall, 1970.
Coulson, Charles A. (1955). Science and Christian Belief,
University of North Carolina Press, 1955.
Coulson, Charles A. (1969). "The Similarity of Science and
Religion"
in Barbour, I. C. (ed.). Science and Religion, Harper and Row, 1969.
Diamond, Malcolm (1974). Contemporary Philosophy and Religions
Thought, McGraw
Hill, 1974.
Durkheim, Emile (1971). Elementary Forms of the Religious
Life, Allen and Unwin, 1971.
Ellul, J. (1964). The Technological Society, Random House, 1964.
Evans, Donald (1963), The Logic of Self-Involvement, SCM, 1963.
Evans, Donald (1968) "Differences Between Scientific and
Religious Assertions"
in Harbour, I. C. (ed.): Science and Religion, Harper and Row, 1968.
Feyerabend, Paul. (1970). "Against Method: Outline of an
Anarchistic Theory
of Knowledge", in Radner, M. and Winoker, S. (Eds.): Minnesota Studies
in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 4, University of Minnesota
Press, 1970.
Gilkey, Langdon (1969). Naming the Whirlwind, Bobbs- Merrill, 1969,
Gilkcy, Langdon (1970). Religion and the Scientific Future,
Harper and Row, 1970.
Greeley, Andrew (1974). Unsecolar Man: The Persistence of
Religion, Dell, 1974.
Harris, Errol (1970). Hypothesis and Perception, The Root of
Scientific Method,
Allen and Unwin, 1970.
Harvey, Van Austin (1966). The Historian and the Believer: The
Morality of Historical
Knowledge and Christian Belief, MacMillan, 1966.
Heim, Karl (1953). Christian Faith and Natural Science, Harper and Brothers, 1953.
Hook, Sydney (1961). The Quest for Being, St. Martin's Press, 1961.
Kierkegaard, 5. (1941). Concluding Unscientific Postscript,
Princeton University Press, 1941.
Kneale, Wm. (1967). "Scientific Revolutions for Ever?",
British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science, 19, 1967.
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University
of Chicago Press, 1962.
Lakatos, Imre (1970). "Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific
Research Programmes", in Lakotos I. and Musgrove R. (eds.):
Criticism and
the Growth of Konwledge, Cambridge University Press, 1970.
Maseal, Eric L. (1965). Christian Theology and Natural Science, Archon Books,
1965.
Miles, T. R. 1959). Religion and the Scientific Outlook, Allen and
Unwin, 1959.
Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science, Routlcdge, Kegan Paul, 1961.
Nash, R. (1963). The Nature of the Natural Sciences, Little, Brown and Co.,
1963,
Polaisyi, Michael (1958). Personal Knowledge: Towards a
PostCritical Philosophy,
Harper and Row, 1958,
Popper, K. R. (1957). The Poverty of Historicism, Routledge, Kegan
Paul, 1957.
Popper, K. R. (1962). The Open Society and Its Enemies (2 vols.), Harper and
Row, 1962.
Ramsey, I. T. (1964). Religion and Science: Conflict and Synthesis,
SPCK, 1964.
Randall, J. H. (1958). The Role of Knowledge in Western Religion, Starr King
Press, 1958.
Scheffler, I. (1967). Science and Subjectivity, Bobbs-Merrill, 1967.
Schiller, F. C. 5. (1955). "Scientific Discovery and Logical
Proof",
in Singer, Charles, (Ed.). Studies in the History and Methods of
the Sciences,
Wm. Dawson and Sons Ltd., 1955.
Schilling, Harold K. (1963), Science and Religion: An Interpretation of Two
Communities, Allen and Unwin, 1963.
Schuon, F, (1975). The Transcendent Unity of Religions, Harper and
Row, 1975.
Slater, Philip (1970). The Pursuit of Loneliness, Beacon Press, 1970.
Slater, Philip (1974). Earthwalk, Doubleday, 1974.
Smarth, Ninian (1969). The Religious Experience of Mankind,
Fontana, 1969,
Smart, Ninian (1973). The Science of Religion and the Sociology of
Knowledge,
Princeton University Press, 1973.
Thakur, S. C. (1970). "Popper on Scientific Method", Philosophical
Studies, 18, 1970.
van Baaren Th. and Drijvers H. (eds.) (1973). Religion, Cul
ture and Methodology, Mouton, 1973.
Wicbe, Don (1976). "Explanation and Theological Method", Zygon, 11,
1976.
Wiebe, Don (1978). "Is a Science of Religion Possible?" Studies in
Religion, 7, 1978.
Wheelis, Allen (1971). The End of the Modern Age, Harper and Row, 1971.
Wheelis, Allen (1974). The Moralist, Penqnin, 1974.
White, Andrew D. (1896), A History of the Warfare of Science with Theology in
Christendom, U. Appleton and Co., 1896.
Yinger, J. Milton (1970). The Scientific Study of Religion,
Macmillan, 1970.
Ziman, J, Ni, (1968). Public Knowledge, Cambridge University Press, 1968.
Zuurdeeg, Wm. F. (1959). An Analytical Philosophy of Religion, Allen and Unwia, 1959.