This page has two main parts, plus “more” and an appendix:
• Do scientists create reality? —
We'll begin by quickly looking at the silly ideas that are proposed
by some scholars, and
are criticized by other
scholars. This
will set a mood
for THE MAIN PART OF THE PAGE and its Essential Concepts:
• Reality 101 — Essential
Concepts
plus more about Reality 101 — Personal
Comments
Appendix: The Limits of Logic,
and Radical Relativism
Do scientists study nature, or create nature? Somewhat amazingly,
Woolgar (1989) argues that scientists construct objects through their representations of them. Objects, according to Woolgar, whether they are countries or electrons, are socially constructed entities, and do not exist aside from this social construction. Science is therefore not the process of finding things that already exist, but the process of creating things that were not there to begin with. (Finkel, 1993, p. 32)
This amazingly silly idea survived for at least 10 years in the mind of Woolgar, because Latour & Woolgar (1979, p. 64) claim that "the bioassay is not merely a means of obtaining some independently given entity; the bioassay constitutes the construction of the substance." This bizarre super-radical constructivism (*) — which also is illustrated when Wheatley (1991, p. 10) declares that "objects do not lie around ready made in the world but are mental constructs" — is criticized by Matthews (1994, p. 152) who explains a crucial distinction: "Where he [Wheatley] goes wrong is in failing to distinguish the theoretical objects of science, which do not lie around, from the real objects of science, which do lie around and fall on people's heads." / * These super-radical claims are an unjustifiable exrapolation of basic constructivist views of learning (which are accepted by most psychologists and educators) so I think the "amazingly silly" claims should be labeled using a different term, not constructivism.
A description of the way scientists typically think about the observation of real objects (no, it is not necessary to "create the reality" of the objects) is provided by a real scientist, a cell biologist:
First, I assume that cells are real objects. Second, I assume that other people can see and think about things the way that I do. ... Others' basic experience of reality is similar to mine. If they were standing where I am standing, they would see something very similar to what I see. ... Scientists act as if...the observations made by one scientist could have been made by anyone and everyone. (Grinnell, 1992, p. 20; emphasis in original)
A prominent philosopher gives another excellent description of truth and its relationship with reality:
Whether a statement is true is an entirely different question from whether you or anybody believes it. ... There can be truths that no one believes. Symmetrically, there can be beliefs that are not true. ... The expression "It's true for me" can be dangerously misleading. Sometimes saying this... means that you believe it. If that's what you want to say, just use the word "belief" and leave truth out of it. However, there is a more radical idea that might be involved here. Someone might use the expression "true for me" to express the idea that each of us makes our own reality and that our beliefs constitute that reality. I will assume that this is a mistake. My concept of truth assumes a fundamental division between the way things really are and the way they seem to be to this or that individual mind. (Sober, 1991, pp. 15-16)
Next, Sober illustrates what he considers to be a valid meaning for "thoughts becoming reality" by describing how a person's thoughts (if he thinks that he won't hit a baseball) can affect his actions (by making him swing too high). By contrast,
What I do deny is that the mere act of thinking, unconnected with action or some other causal pathway, can make statements true. I'm rejecting the idea that the world is arranged so that it spontaneously conforms to the ideas we may happen to entertain. (Sober, 1991, p. 16)
These quotations, from Grinnell and Sober, a scientist and a philosopher, summarize the most important concepts of Reality 101 — in the distinction between humanly-constructed realities (our beliefs, scientific theories, baseball actions, plus cultures & values,...) and human-independent realities (electrons, bioassays, objects, or planets,...) so I'll just close this section with an example from science: Anyone who really thinks that "beliefs create reality" should be eager to explain how the real motions of all planets in the solar system changed from earth-centered orbits in 1500 (when this was believed by almost everyone) to sun-centered orbits in 1700 (when this was believed by almost all scientists). Did the change in beliefs (from theories of 1500 to theories of 1700) cause a change in reality (with planets beginning to orbit the sun at some time – but exactly when did this occur – between 1500 and 1700) ?
This section — Do scientists create reality? — is adapted from Section 4C of a page asking "Should
scientific method be eks-rated?"
The Solar System Question
To
illustrate important ideas about truth and
truth-claims,
let's
begin with a famous example: Between
1500 (when almost everyone believed that the sun and planets revolved
around the earth) and 1700 (when almost every educated person believed
that the earth and planets revolved around the sun), what changed and
what did not change?
Did the reality change? Did
the motions of planets change from earth-centered (in 1500) to sun-centered
(in 1700)? No.
Did the truth change? No. Because
truth is determined by reality, what was true in 1500 (the earth and
planets really moved around the sun) was also true in 1700.
Did our truth-claims change? Yes. Our
humanly constructed beliefs about the motions were different in 1500 and
1700. Thus, there were changes in the realities of humanly-constructed
science, philosophy, religion, and culture, as explained below.
Two
Types of Reality
During
the 200 years between 1500 and 1700, some aspects of reality did change. For
example, in 1500 scientists said "of course" when a scholar stated that
everything revolves around the earth, but in 1700 they laughed at a scholar
making the same
statement. This
change in response, from acceptance to ridicule, was due to a real change
in a humanly constructed theory, which produced a real change in a humanly
constructed social context. By contrast, another aspect of reality
(involving the motions of earth, sun, and planets) was not humanly constructed. This "solar
system reality" was independent of humans, and it did not change
when we changed. There is an important difference between humanly-constructed reality and human-independent reality.
A modern example of humanly constructed
reality is the societal agreement, adopted by consensus and institutionalized
in traffic laws, that we will stop at a red light, and that in America (and
in continental Europe but not Britain or Japan) we will drive on the right
side of the road.
But if there is a collision, due to
someone running a red light or driving on the wrong side or making some other
mistake, humans do not construct the laws of physics that determine what
happens during the collision. Yes, we can minimize the harmful results
of a collision by constructing cars with air bags, collapsible bumpers, and
other safety features. But we achieve this humanly-constructed reality (in which we have safer cars) by acknowledging and understanding a human-independent
reality (involving the physics of collisions). We can build safer cars
by cooperating with reality, by designing cars within the context of the
physics that really exists. But we cannot build safer cars by denying
this reality, by trying to overcome it through faith in a kinder-and-gentler
physics we have constructed; during a collison we would prefer this
physics, but we cannot produce it.
If we recognize the existence
of two types of reality — independent and constructed — our worldview
is less simple than if we ignore this distinction and lump everything together
into one category. But a view that "splits" instead of "lumping" will
see things in a way that is more accurate, and will avoid the confusions that
occur when we try to think about both types of reality in the same way.
Our thinking and communicating
should be different for the two types of reality. Some ideas about "beliefs
creating reality" are rational for humanly constructed realities (for
example, deciding whether to praise or ridicule a scholar, or deciding whether
to drive through an intersection or stop) but these ideas are ludicrous for independent
realities (such
as the motions in our solar system) in which reality is not affected by belief
or social agreement.
This distinction will also
help us understand the correct causal relationships. Yes, our thoughts
and actions do cause consequences when "what we think and do" is converted
into constructed reality. But for independent reality, our
believing that something is true does not cause it to be true. { We
can believe that an independent reality is true because it is true (if
the consequences of its existence-and-operation produce evidence that persuades
us of its existence-and-operation) but the correct sequence of causation
is "reality
--> evidence --> belief", not "belief --> reality". }
note: Some highly speculative
interpretations of quantum mechanics claim that human observation (or human
consciousness) can directly affect reality. But in a page about quantum
physics and reality I
use principles of quantum physics to explain why these "mystical
physics" claims are not supported by science and why, at the quantum level
and everyday level, human actions can affect some aspects of reality but
not other aspects.
This distinction is also helpful
when we ask, "Are scientific theories constructed or discovered?" Contemporary
scholars claim that scientific theories
are humanly constructed,
and this is true, but only in some ways. Yes, between 1500 and 1700
our
theories
about the solar system were constructed and they did change. But
our theories
improved
because
we discovered more
about an independent
reality that was not constructed by us. In order to construct accurate
theories about a human-independent reality (like the solar system)
our
theory
construction
must
be constrained and guided by what we discover about this reality. By contrast,
if sociologists are
constructing
theories
about a society that is a humanly-constructed reality,
there
will
be
interactions between theories they are constructing and the reality they
are describing-and-explaining,
which (if the sociologists and their theories are influential in society) will
let
them
help "construct
the
reality" of the society. But
they can do this only because society is a humanly-constructed
reality, not a human-independent reality
Does it matter? Yes, the distinction between independent reality and constructed reality is extremely important. A failure to make this distinction, or a stubborn refusal to make it, will cause confusion. Therefore, if we want our thinking to be more precise and less confused, we will always ask "Which type of reality is it?"
Because "absolute truth" is overpopulated
with potential meanings, which can lead to confusion and misuderstanding, we
should avoid this term (by replacing it with terms whose meaning is
more precise) or clearly explain the intended meaning.
Sometimes absolute
truth and relative truth are replaced
by Truth (with a capital T) and truth (with
a small t) but this isn't useful because many meanings are possible, so we
don't know the intended meanings of Truth and truth. And this pair
of terms has an extra disadvantage, because "truth" is used in
a way that, in my opinion, it should never be used.
Similarly, the meaning of
a Biblical truth is not clear. It
would be more accurate to say that you think the Bible makes this truth-claim
about reality (about some aspect of the spiritual realm, or human history,
or a Bible-based principle for living,...) because this will clarify
the intended meaning.
Confidence
and Truth
In science — as
in most other areas of life (*) — proof is
impossible, but scientists can develop a rationally
justified confidence in
the truth or falsity of a theory. Why is proof impossible, and how
can scientists develop confidence? This is discussed in The
Limits of Logic, which explains why modern
science has given up the quest for certainty, and has decided to aim for
a high degree
of plausibility, for a rational way to determine "what is a good way
to bet." {* In
some areas, proof is possible. For example, in mathematics we can prove
that "2 + 3 = 5" if we define each of the five concepts ( 2 , +
, 3 , = , 5 ) as in our usual system of math. But in science,
and for the important questions in life, proof is
impossible. }
In most situations the perspective
of most scientists is a critical realism
that combines realist goals (wanting
to find the truth) with critical evaluation (willing
to be skeptical about the truth-claims associated with a particular theory).
Our degree
of confidence in a theory can be summarized in its theory
status, which is an estimate of a theory's plausibility. * This
concept is useful because it allows flexibility in our thinking. If
status is extremely high or low, we can choose to accept or reject a
theory. But we have options because, in addition to this binary yes-or-no
choice, we can also think in terms of a status (a degree
of confidence)
that can vary along a continuum ranging from high to low, from yes to no,
with varying degrees of confidence between these extremes. An important
part of a truth-claim is the confidence assigned
to it by the claimer; there is a difference between claiming "maybe
this is true" and "I'm certain this is true." {* Our
estimates
of a
theory's utility can supplement
our estimates of its plausibility when
we are evaluating theory status. }
Thinking about theory status,
with degrees of confidence, makes it easier to view theories with a logically
appropriate humility because we can avoid the extremes of a
silly radical
relativism (which insists that if we cannot claim certainty, we can
claim nothing) and the over-reaction that produces arrogantly overconfident
claims (in thinking that if we want to avoid the extreme of not claiming any
confidence, we must claim the total confidence of certainty). An appropriate
humility recognizes that, based on evidence and logic, in some situations only
a low level of confidence is justifiable, while in other situations a high
degree of
confidence
(which
is almost a certainty) is justified.
Is relativism illogical and
self-refuting? Some
of its critics make this claim, but I disagree. To
see why, let's
look at two assertions that could be made
by a
relativist:
1) A statement that "all theories
are false" is inconsistent and incorrect,
because the statement is itself a theory, so if the
statement is true, then at least one theory is true, and the
statement is false.
2) A statement that "all theories
are uncertain" is not internally inconsistent because when
you say "if
you are correct, then your own theory is uncertain and you can't be certain
about its truth" the claimer will agree that "yes, this is
what I said."
#1 is logically self-refuting,
but this isn't the claim usually being made by relativists. Instead
they claim #2 (which is not logically self-refuting) by saying "we
can never be certain about anything" or,
with more humility, "I'm not certain that we can ever be certain
about anything."
In fact, I agree with #2 because "proof
is impossible." But the difficulty with postmodernism
is that "if a good idea is taken to extremes...
there may be undesirable consequences," as explained later. Yes, "proof is
impossible" but rationally
justified confidence is possible,
and sometimes "a high degree of confidence
(which is almost a certainty) is justified."
Unfortunately, some
Christians claim that "relativism
is self-refuting" in a well-intended
but futile attempt to find a simple flaw in postmodern relativism. I
think serious flaws do exist, but they are not simple and obvious, so careful
thinking is required.
On the other
hand, a claim that "it's
wrong to say someone is wrong" is logically inconsistent, as discussed later
when we ask "Is it wrong to say ‘I think you're wrong’?" and
we compare
The New Tolerance with
Conventional Tolerance. }
We began this page by asking"Do
scientists create reality?" and
we've been looking at relationships between confidence and truth, including
these: when
strong confidence seems justified, this confidence will not affect a human-independent
reality; and
when a general humility seems justified and we are not highly confident about
any current theory,
truth
does exist
even though
we don't
know what
is
true.
a
scientific example: In
1600, based on the best available evidence and logic, a sun-centered theory
deserved an intermediate status, and it received a mixed reception. Some
scholars argued for it, others were against it, and everyone was able to support
their view with evidence, logic, and philosophy. During a 200-year period,
from 1500 to 1700, the human consensus changed from almost-certainty (but with
a mismatch between confidence
and truth, due to
widespread belief
in a theory
that
was wrong) to intermediate levels of confidence (that gradually, due to new
evidence and improved analysis, shifted in favor of a sun-centered theory)
back to almost-certainty (with belief in a theory that we now claim, with
a high degree of confidence that approaches certainty, actually is true). But
during these changes in humanly constructed theories about truth, the actual
truth — which
was determined by human-independent reality, by the actual motions of the earth,
planets, and sun — remained
what it was, unchanged by human debates.
a spiritual
example: Based
on the Bible, Christians claim that God created the universe, and Jesus was
resurrected
from the dead. * Are these claims
true or false? This depends only
on reality, on what actually happened in history. Because these claims
are about independent reality, their truth or falsity does not depend on
what you or I choose to believe. But
each of us has a worldview, which includes our beliefs about claims made
in the Bible, and this "personally
constructed internal reality" does influence our attitudes and actions. {* But
we should be cautious about other claims — such as those made in
1633
(about
an
earth-centered
solar system) and 2007 (about a young earth) — that are not important theologically,
and have
led
to
a
common
perception of inherent conflict (and even "war") between science
and
religion. These
claims about "science in the Bible" are discussed in Science-Religion
Conflict? (flat earth & Galileo) and an
introduction to modern conflicts
caused by young-earth
claims and Biblical Theology
for young-earth
Christians. }
Confidence
and Faith
Can
we have faith without proof? Yes,
we have faith if we have personal confidence in God, as explained
in a page that asks "Why isn't
God more obvious? Can we prove God?" and concludes with a summary:
Truth
does exist, even though we cannot know with absolute certainty what this
truth is. ...
Despite the impossibility
of proof, evidence [historical, scientific, personal, interpersonal]
can affect our estimates for the plausibility of various worldviews. ...
I'm not advocating a spiritual
agnosticism that claims "if there is not enough evidence for certainty,
the most rational decision is to not decide." ... I'm merely suggesting
that we humbly recognize the limits of logical persuasion and the impossibility
of proof, and see
our world as an environment that permits free decisions and provides
opportunities for living by faith in whatever worldview a person has
decided to construct
and accept. ...
God wants us to live by faith...
by making daily decisions on the basis of trust in God's character and
promises.
A strong faith is consistent with a humble
recognition that other people, thinking rationally, can reach different conclusions
about the worldview they have chosen to "live by faith."
SUMMARY
When there is
a question or discussion about truth, ask yourself:
Are we thinking about the
truth (which
is determined by reality) or a
truth-claim (which is a human theory about reality)?
Is the reality analogous to movements
in the solar system (human-independent reality) or is it like driving
on a specified side of the road (humanly constructed reality)? These
two types of reality have different characteristics, and claims that are
rational for one type can be silly for the other type.
For either type of reality, the certainty
of logically rigorous proof is impossible, but logically justifiable
confidence is possible.
For human-independent reality,
a high level of confidence in a theory cannot make it true. But even
though we cannot control the independent reality of our solar system, we
(individually and in groups)
do "construct our reality" when we construct our worldviews and
partially construct our situations. { I say "partially" because
some aspects of our situations are beyond our control. } But
even though the truth of a theory is not affected by our confidence that
the
theory is true (or is false), our confidence — if it is based
on a solid foundation of evidence and logic — may be an indication
that the theory is true (or is false).
The questions, "does God exist?" and "does
God set standards for our behavior?", are about independent realities. But
another question, "should we use the standards of God (as described in
the Bible) as the basis for our individual and societal behavior?", is
about humanly constructed reality.
more about Reality 101 — Personal Commentary In
contrast with the main "Reality 101" which is foundational summary
of basic ideas, the sections below — about Postmodernism and Reality
909 — is a personal commentary. It
contains ideas that I hope will stimulate your thinking, but is rough-and-incomplete,
is not self-contained (since it assumes you're already familiar with
the basic ideas of modernism and
postmodernism that are described in other
pages), and is not intended to provide an in-depth
comprehensive
analysis of the complex issues being examined. But
I think you'll find it interesting and useful. Reflections on Postmodernism (and Modernism)
Postmodernists emphasize
the importance of language, which affects how we think and how we interact
with each other. Yes, language is important in our thinking,
communicating, and constructing of theories, as discussed in "Using
Precise Language" above. Postmodernists are skillfully using
language to support their views and increase their influence. Non-postmodernists
should pay more attention to the uses of language in society.
|
This website for Whole-Person Education has TWO KINDS OF LINKS:
an ITALICIZED LINK keeps you inside a page, moving you to another part of it, and a NON-ITALICIZED LINK opens another page. Both keep everything inside this window, so your browser's BACK-button will always take you back to where you were. |
Tolerance and Truth Modern Quantum Physics: What about Einstein's Theory of Invariance? Should "scientific method" be eks-rated? Worldview Education for Christian Living OTHER PAGES |
This page is
http://www.asa3.org/ASA/education/views/reality.htm
Copyright © 2003 by Craig Rusbult
all rights reserved